Psychology Wiki
Advertisement

Assessment | Biopsychology | Comparative | Cognitive | Developmental | Language | Individual differences | Personality | Philosophy | Social |
Methods | Statistics | Clinical | Educational | Industrial | Professional items | World psychology |

Philosophy Index: Aesthetics · Epistemology · Ethics · Logic · Metaphysics · Consciousness · Philosophy of Language · Philosophy of Mind · Philosophy of Science · Social and Political philosophy · Philosophies · Philosophers · List of lists


This article needs rewriting to enhance its relevance to psychologists..
Please help to improve this page yourself if you can..


For the work by Aristotle, see Metaphysics (Aristotle).
Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle

Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), by Raphael (Stanza della Segnatura, Rome)

Metaphysics investigates principles of reality transcending those of any particular science. Cosmology and ontology are traditional branches of metaphysics. It is concerned with explaining the fundamental nature of being and the world.[1] Someone who studies metaphysics can be called either a "metaphysician" or a "metaphysicist".[2]

The word derives from the Greek words μετά (metá) (meaning "beyond" or "after") and φυσικά (physiká) (meaning "physical"), "physical" referring to those works on matter by Aristotle in antiquity. The prefix meta- ("beyond") was attached to the chapters in Aristotle's work that physically followed after the chapters on "physics", in posthumously edited collections. Aristotle himself did not call these works Metaphysics. Aristotle called some of the subjects treated there "first philosophy".

A central branch of metaphysics is ontology, the investigation into what types of things there are in the world and what relations these things bear to one another. The metaphysician also attempts to clarify the notions by which people understand the world, including existence, objecthood, property, space, time, causality, and possibility.

Before the development of modern science, scientific questions were addressed as a part of metaphysics known as "natural philosophy"; the term "science" itself meant "knowledge" of epistemological origin. The scientific method, however, made natural philosophy an empirical and experimental activity unlike the rest of philosophy, and by the end of the eighteenth century it had begun to be called "science" in order to distinguish it from philosophy. Thereafter, metaphysics became the philosophical enquiry of a non-empirical character into the nature of existence. Thus the original situation of metaphysics being integral with (Aristotelian) physics and science, has, in the West, become reversed so that scientists often consider metaphysics antithetical to the empirical sciences.

History of metaphysics[]

One of the first metaphysicians is Parmenides of Elea. He held that the multiplicity of existing things, their changing forms and motion, are but an appearance of a single eternal reality (“Being”),thus giving rise to the Parmenidean principle that “all is one”. From this concept of Being, he went on to say that all claims of change or of non-Being are illogical. Because he introduced the method of basing claims about appearances on a logical concept of Being, he is considered one of the founders of metaphysics. [3]

Metaphysics is called the "first philosophy" by Aristotle.The editor of his works, Andronicus of Rhodes, is thought to have placed the books on first philosophy right after another work, Physics, and called them τὰ μετὰ τὰ φυσικὰ βιβλία (ta meta ta physika biblia) or "the books that come after the [books on] physics". This was misread by Latin scholiasts, who thought it meant "the science of what is beyond the physical".[4] In the English language, the word comes by way of the Medieval Latin metaphysica, the neuter plural of Medieval Greek metaphysika.[5] While its Greek and Latin origins are clear, various dictionaries trace its first appearance in English to the mid-sixteenth century, although in some cases as early as 1387.[5][6]

Aristotle's Metaphysics was divided into three parts, in addition to some smaller sections related to a philosophical lexicon and some reprinted extracts from the Physics, which are now regarded as the proper branches of traditional Western metaphysics:

Ontology
The study of Being and existence; includes the definition and classification of entities, physical or mental, the nature of their properties, and the nature of change.
Natural Theology
The study of a God or Gods; involves many topics, including among others the nature of religion and the world, existence of the divine, questions about Creation, and the numerous religious or spiritual issues that concern humankind in general.
Universal science
The study of first principles, which Aristotle believed to be the foundation of all other inquiries. An example of such a principle is the law of noncontradiction and the status it holds in non-paraconsistent logics.

Universal science or first philosophy treats of "being qua being"—that is, what is basic to all science before one adds the particular details of any one science. Essentially "being qua being" may be translated as "being insofar as being goes" or as "being in terms of being". This includes topics such as causality, substance, species and elements, as well as the notions of relation, interaction, and finitude.

Metaphysics as a discipline was a central part of academic inquiry and scholarly education even before the age of Aristotle, who considered it "the Queen of Sciences". Its issues were considered no less important than the other main formal subjects of physical science, medicine, mathematics, poetics and music. Since the beginning of modern philosophy during the seventeenth century, problems that were not originally considered within the bounds of metaphysics have been added to its purview, while other problems considered metaphysical for centuries are now typically relegated to their own separate regions in philosophy, such as philosophy of religion, philosophy of mind, philosophy of perception, philosophy of language, and philosophy of science.

In some cases, subjects of metaphysical scholarship have been found to be entirely physical and natural, thus making them part of physics proper (cf. Albert Einstein's Theory of Relativity).

Central questions of metaphysics[]

Most positions that can be taken with regards to any of the following questions are endorsed by one or another notable philosopher.It is often difficult to frame the questions in a non-controversial manner.

Abstract objects and mathematics[]

Some philosophers endorse views according to which there are abstract objects such as numbers, or Universals. (Universals are properties that can be instantiated by multiple objects, such as redness or squareness.) Abstract objects are generally regarded as being outside of space and time, and/or as being causally inert. Mathematical objects and fictional entities and worlds are often given as examples of abstract objects. The view that there really are no abstract objects is called nominalism. Realism about such objects is exemplified by Platonism. Other positions include moderate realism, as espoused by Aristotle, and conceptualism.

The philosophy of mathematics overlaps with metaphysics because some positions are realistic in the sense that they hold that mathematical objects really exist, whether transcendentally, physically, or mentally. Platonic realism holds that mathematical entities are a transcendent realm of non-physical objects. The simplest form of mathematical empiricism claims that mathematical objects are just ordinary physical objects, i.e. that squares and the like physically exist. Plato rejected this view, among other reasons, because geometrical figures in mathematics have a perfection that no physical instantiation can capture. Modern mathematicians have developed many strange and complex mathematical structures with no counterparts in observable reality, further supporting Plato's view. The third main form of realism holds that mathematical entities exist in the mind. However, given a materialistic conception of the mind, it does not have the capacity to literally contain the many infinities of objects in mathematics. Intuitionism, inspired by Kant, sticks with the idea that "there are no non-experienced mathematical truths". This involves rejecting as intuitionistically unacceptable anything that cannot be held in the mind or explicitly constructed. Intuitionists reject the law of the excluded middle and are suspicious of infinity, particularly of transfinite numbers.

Other positions such as formalism and fictionalism that do not attribute any existence to mathematical entities are anti-realist.

Cosmology and cosmogony[]

See also: Cosmology (metaphysics)

Cosmology is the branch of metaphysics that deals with the world as the totality of all phenomena in space and time. Historically, it has had quite a broad scope, and in many cases was founded in religion. The ancient Greeks did not draw a distinction between this use and their model for the cosmos. However, in modern use it addresses questions about the Universe which are beyond the scope of physical science. It is distinguished from religious cosmology in that it approaches these questions using philosophical methods (e.g. dialectics). Cosmogony deals specifically with the origin of the universe.

Modern metaphysical cosmology and cosmogony try to address questions such as:

  • What is the origin of the Universe? What is its first cause? Is its existence necessary? (see monism, pantheism, emanationism and creationism)
  • What are the ultimate material components of the Universe? (see mechanism, dynamism, hylomorphism, atomism)
  • What is the ultimate reason for the existence of the Universe? Does the cosmos have a purpose? (see teleology)

Determinism and free will[]

See also: Determinism and Free will

Determinism is the philosophical proposition that every event, including human cognition, decision and action, is causally determined by an unbroken chain of prior occurrences. It holds that no random, spontaneous, mysterious, or miraculous events occur. The principal consequence of the deterministic claim is that it poses a challenge to the existence of free will.

The problem of free will is the problem of whether rational agents exercise control over their own actions and decisions. Addressing this problem requires understanding the relation between freedom and causation, and determining whether the laws of nature are causally deterministic. Some philosophers, known as Incompatibilists, view determinism and free will as mutually exclusive. If they believe in determinism, they will therefore believe free will to be an illusion, a position known as Hard Determinism. Proponents range from Baruch Spinoza to Ted Honderich.

Others, labeled Compatibilists (or "Soft Determinists"), believe that the two ideas can be coherently reconciled. Adherents of this view include Thomas Hobbes and many modern philosophers.

Incompatibilists who accept free will but reject determinism are called Libertarians, a term not to be confused with the political sense. Robert Kane is a modern defender of this theory.

It is a popular misconception that determinism necessarily entails that humanity or individual humans have no influence on the future and its events ( a position known as Fatalism). Determinists, however, believe that the level to which human beings have influence over their future is itself dependent on present and past.

Identity and change[]

Main article: Identity and change
See also: Identity (philosophy) and Philosophy of space and time

The Greeks took some extreme positions on the nature of change: Parmenides denied that change occurs at all, while Heraclitus thought change was ubiquitous: "[Y]ou cannot step into the same river twice".

Identity, sometimes called Numerical Identity, is the relation that a "thing" bears to itself, and which no "thing" bears to anything other than itself (cf. sameness). According to Leibniz, if some object x is identical to some object y, then any property that x has, y will have as well. However, it seems, too, that objects can change over time. If one were to look at a tree one day, and the tree later lost a leaf, it would seem that one could still be looking at that same tree. Two rival theories to account for the relationship between change and identity are Perdurantism, which treats the tree as a series of tree-stages, and Endurantism which maintains that the tree -- the same tree -- is present at every stage in its history.

Mind and matter[]

The nature of matter was a problem in its own right in early philosophy. Aristotle himself introduced the idea of matter in general to the Western world, adapting the term hyle which originally meant "lumber". Early debates centered on identifying a single underlying principle. Water was claimed by Thales, Air by Anaximenes, Apeiron (the Boundless) by Anaximander, Fire by Heraclitus. Democritus, in conjunction with his mentor, Leucippus, conceived of an atomic theory many centuries before it was accepted by modern science. It is worth noting, however, that the grounds necessary to ensure validity to the proposed theory's veridical nature were not scientific, but just as philosophical as those traditions espoused by Thales and Anaximander.

Philosophers now look to empirical science for insights into the nature of matter.

The nature of the mind and its relation to the body has been seen as more of a problem as science has progressed in its mechanistic understanding of the brain and body. Proposed solutions often have ramifications about the nature of mind as a whole. René Descartes proposed substance dualism, a theory in which mind and body are essentially quite different, with the mind having some of the attributes traditionally assigned to the soul, in the seventeenth century. This creates a conceptual puzzle about how the two interact (which has received some strange answers, such as occasionalism). Evidence of a close relationship between brain and mind, such as the Phineas Gage case, have made this form of dualism increasingly unpopular.

Another proposal discussing the mind-body problem is idealism, in which the material is sweepingly eliminated in favor of the mental. Idealists, such as George Berkeley, claim that material objects do not exist unless perceived and only as perceptions. The "German idealists" such as Fichte, Hegel and Schopenhauer took Kant as their starting-point, although it is debatable how much of an idealist Kant himself was. Idealism is also a common theme in Eastern philosophy. Related ideas are panpsychism and panexperientialism which say everything has a mind rather than everything exists in a mind. Alfred North Whitehead was a twentieth-century exponent of this approach.

Idealism is a monistic theory, in which there is a single universal substance or principles. Neutral monism, associated in different forms with Baruch Spinoza and Bertrand Russell is a theory which seeks to be less extreme than idealism, and to avoid the problems of substance dualism. It claims that existence consists of a single substance, which in itself is neither mental nor physical, but is capable of mental and physical aspects or attributes – thus it implies a dual-aspect theory.

For the last one hundred years, the dominant metaphysics has without a doubt been materialistic monism. Type identity theory, token identity theory, functionalism, reductive physicalism, nonreductive physicalism, eliminative materialism, anomalous monism, property dualism, epiphenomenalism and emergence are just some of the candidates for a scientifically-informed account of the mind. (It should be noted that while many of these positions are dualisms, none of them are substance dualism.)

Prominent recent philosophers of mind include David Armstrong, Ned Block, David Chalmers, Patricia and Paul Churchland, Donald Davidson, Daniel Dennett, Douglas Hofstadter, Jerry Fodor, David Lewis, Thomas Nagel, Hilary Putnam, John Searle, John Smart and Ludwig Wittgenstein.

Necessity and possibility[]

See also: Modal logic and Modal realism

Metaphysicians investigate questions about the ways the world could have been. David Lewis, in "On the Plurality of Worlds," endorsed a view called Concrete Modal realism, according to which facts about how things could have been are made true by other concrete worlds, just like ours, in which things are different. Other philosophers, such as Gottfried Leibniz, have dealt with the idea of possible worlds as well. The idea of necessity is that any necessary fact is true across all possible worlds; that is, we could not imagine it to be otherwise. A possible fact is true in some possible world, even if not in the actual world. For example, it is possible that cats could have had two tails, or that any particular apple could have not existed. By contrast, certain propositions seem necessarily true, such as analytic propositions, e.g. "All bachelors are unmarried." The particular example of analytic truth being necessary is not universally held among philosophers. A less controversial view might be that self-identity is necessary, as it seems fundamentally incoherent to claim that for any x, it is not identical to itself; this is known as the law of identity, a putative "first principle". Aristotle describes the principle of non-contradiction, "It is impossible that the same quality should both belong and not belong to the same thing . . . This is the most certain of all principles . . . Wherefore they who demonstrate refer to this as an ultimate opinion. For it is by nature the source of all the other axioms."

Objects and their properties[]

Further information: Problem of universals

The world seems to contain many individual things, both physical, like apples, and abstract such as love and the number 3; the former objects are called particulars. Particulars are said to have attributes, e.g. size, shape, color, location and two particulars may have some such attributes in common. Such attributes, are also termed Universals or Properties; the nature of these, and whether they have any real existence and if so of what kind, is a long-standing issue, realism and nominalism representing opposing views.

Metaphysicians concerned with questions about universals or particulars are interested in the nature of objects and their properties, and the relationship between the two. Some, e.g. Plato, argue that properties are abstract objects, existing outside of space and time, to which particular objects bear special relations. David Armstrong holds that universals exist in time and space but only at their instantiation and their discovery is a function of science. Others maintain that what particulars are is a bundle or collection of properties (specifically, a bundle of properties they have).

Religion and spirituality[]

Theology is the study of a God or gods and the nature of the divine. Whether there is a God (monotheism), many gods (polytheism) or no gods (atheism), or whether it is unknown or unknowable whether any gods exist (agnosticism), and whether the Divine intervenes directly in the world (theism), or its sole function is to be the first cause of the universe (deism); these and whether a God or gods and the World are different (as in panentheism and dualism), or are identical (as in pantheism), are some of the primary metaphysical questions concerning philosophy of religion.

Within the standard Western philosophical tradition, theology reached its peak under the medieval school of thought known as scholasticism, which focused primarily on the metaphysical aspects of Christianity. While the work of the scholastics has been largely eclipsed in the wake of modern philosophy, key figures such as Thomas Aquinas still play an important role in the philosophy of religion.[How to reference and link to summary or text]

Space and time[]

Further information: Philosophy of space and time

In the Middle Ages, Saint Augustine of Hippo asked the fundamental question about the nature of time. A traditional realist position in ontology is that time and space have existence apart from the human mind. Idealists, including Kant claim that space and time are mental constructs used to organise perceptions, or are otherwise unreal.

Suppose that one is sitting at a table, with an apple in front of him or her; the apple exists in space and in time, but what does this statement indicate? Could it be said, for example, that space is like an invisible three-dimensional grid in which the apple is positioned? Suppose the apple, and all physical objects in the universe, were removed from existence entirely. Would space as an "invisible grid" still exist? René Descartes and Leibniz believed it would not, arguing that without physical objects, "space" would be meaningless because space is the framework upon which we understand how physical objects are related to each other. Newton, on the other hand, argued for an absolute "container" space. The pendulum swung back to relational space with Einstein and Ernst Mach.

While the absolute/relative debate, and the realism debate are equally applicable to time and space, time presents some special problems of its own. The flow of time has been denied in ancient times by Parmenides and more recently by J. M. E. McTaggart in his paper The Unreality of Time.

The direction of time, also known as "time's arrow", is also a puzzle, although physics is now driving the debate rather than philosophy. It appears that fundamental laws are time-reversible and the arrow of time must be an "emergent" phenomenon, perhaps explained by a statistical understanding of thermodynamic entropy.

Common-sense tells us that objects persist across time, that there is some sense in which you are the same person you were yesterday, in which the oak is the same as the acorn, in which you perhaps even can step into the same river twice. Philosophers have developed two rival theories for how this happens, called "endurantism" and "perdurantism". Broadly speaking, endurantists hold that a whole object exists at each moment of its history, and the same object exists at each moment. Perdurantists believe that objects are four-dimensional entities made up of a series of temporal parts like the frames of a movie.

Criticism[]

Metaphysics has been continuously contended in history as vague or untrue.

David Hume argued with his empiricist principle that all knowledge involves either relations of ideas or matters of fact:

If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion.

An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

Hume's assertion, it has been argued, is self-defeating if it itself is not self-evident or empirically verifiable.

Immanuel Kant prescribed a limited role to the subject and argued against knowledge progressing beyond the world of our representations, except to knowledge that the noumena exist:

...though we cannot know these objects as things in themselves, we must yet be in a position at least to think them as things in themselves; otherwise we should be landed in the absurd conclusion that there can be appearance without anything that appears.

Critique of Pure Reason pp. Bxxvi-xxvii

A.J. Ayer in "Language, Truth and Logic" using the verifiability theory of meaning concluded that metaphysical propositions were neither true nor false but strictly meaningless, as were religious views.

Karl Popper argued that metaphysical statements are not meaningless statements, but rather not fallible, testable or provable statements [How to reference and link to summary or text] i.e. neither empirical observations nor logical arguments could prove metaphysical statements to be true or false. Hence, a metaphysical statement usually implies an idea about the world or about the universe, which may seem reasonable but is ultimately not empirically testable.

Disciplines, topics and problems[]

Main article: List of metaphysics articles
  1. REDIRECT Template:Multicol

Disciplines

|

|}


See also[]

Notes and references[]

  1. Geisler, Norman L. "Baker Encyclopedia of Christian Apologetics" page 446. Baker Books, 1999
  2. Random House Dictionary Online
  3. Encyclopedia Britannica Online
  4. However, once the name was given, the commentators sought to find intrinsic reasons for its appropriateness. For instance, it was understood to mean "the science of the world beyond nature", that is, the science of the immaterial. Again, it was understood to refer to the chronological or pedagogical order among our philosophical studies, so that the "metaphysical sciences would mean, those which we study after having mastered the sciences which deal with the physical world" (St. Thomas, "In Lib, Boeth. de Trin.", V, 1). In the widespread, though erroneous, use of the term in current popular literature, there is a remnant of the notion that metaphysical means ultraphysical: thus, "metaphysical healing" means healing by means of remedies which are not physical. Template:CathEncy
  5. 5.0 5.1 Douglas Harper. Online Etymology Dictionary. URL accessed on August 29 2006.
  6. Unabridged Dictionary. URL accessed on August 29 2006.


Further reading[]

Key texts[]

Books[]

  • Barnard, G. W. (1998). William James and the origins of mystical experience. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Buckle, H. T. (1920). Examination of the method employed by metaphysicians for discovering mental laws. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Butchvarov, P. (1979). Being Qua Being: A Theory of Identity, Existence and Predication. Bloomington and London: Indiana University Press.
  • Gale, Richard M. (2002). The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics. Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Gill, M. M., & Holzman, P. S. (1976). Psychology versus metapsychology: Psychoanalytic essays in memory of George S. Klein. Oxford, England: International U Press.
  • Gillett, C. (2003). Non-reductive realization and non-reductive identity: What physicalism does not entail. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Gillett, C. (2007). The metaphysics of mechanisms and the challenge of the new reductionism. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
  • Harris, E. E. (1965). The Foundations of Metaphysics in Science. London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Harris, E. E. (2000). The Restitution of Metaphysics. New York: Humanity Books.
  • Hattiangadi, J. (2005). The Mind as an Object of Scientific Study. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Heller, M. (2006). Science and Transcendence: Limits of Language and Common Sense. West Conshohocken, PA: Templeton Foundation Press.
  • James, W. (1892). Epilogue: Psychology and philosophy. Ny: Henry Holt and Company.
  • James, W. (1907). Lecture III: Some metaphysical problems pragmatically considered. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • James, W. (1913). Necessary truths and the effects of experience. New York, NY: Henry Holt and Co.
  • Jibu, M., & Yasue, K. (2004). Quantum Brain Dynamics and Quantum Field Theory. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Kant, I., & Meiklejohn, J. M. D. (1899). Critique of pure reason. New York, NY: Willey Book Co.
  • Kant, I., & Meiklejohn, J. M. D. (1899). The history of pure reason. New York, NY: Willey Book Co.
  • Kant, I., & Meiklejohn, J. M. D. (1899). Part first--Transcendental aesthetic. New York, NY: Willey Book Co.
  • Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa Ed. (1999). Metaphysics: An Anthology. Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies.
  • Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa, Ed. (2000). A Companion to Metaphysics. Malden Massachusetts, Blackwell, Publishers.
  • Lange, F. A., & Thomas, E. C. (1880). Philosophical materialism since Kant. Boston, MA: Houghton, Osgood, & Company.
  • Legerstee, M. (1999). Mental and bodily awareness in infancy: Consciousness of self-existence. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Loeb, J. (1900). Cerebral hemispheres and associative memory. New York, NY: G P Putnam's Sons.
  • Loewald, H. W. (1988). Psychoanalysis in search of nature: Thoughts on metapsychology, "metaphysics," projection. Madison, CT: International Universities Press, Inc.
  • Lotze, H. (1888). Knowledge and truth. Edinburgh, Great Britain: T & T Clark.
  • Lowe, E. J. (2003). Physical causal closure and the invisibility of mental causation. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Lowe, E. J. (2002). A Survey of Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Loux, M. J. (2006). Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction (3rd ed.). London: Routledge.
  • Mach, E., & Williams, C. M. (1897). Introductory remarks: Antimetaphysical. Chicago, IL: The Open Court Publishing Company.
  • Mackintosh, R. (1899). The metaphysics of natural selection. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Magnin, T. (2006). Moral Philosophy: A Space for Dialogue between Science and Theology. West Conshohocken, PA: Templeton Foundation Press.
  • Mahon, B. Z., & Caramazza, A. (2007). The organization and representation of conceptual knowledge in the brain: Living kinds and artifacts. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Medin, D. L., & Rips, L. J. (2005). Concepts and Categories: Memory, Meaning, and Metaphysics. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Melnyk, A. (2003). Some evidence for physicalism. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Menzies, P. (2003). The causal efficacy of mental states. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Midgley, M. (1999). Being scientific about our selves. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Montero, B. (2003). Varieties of causal closure. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Moore, G. (1852). The connection of the mind with the brain, etc. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Morris, G. S. (1882). The futility of "metaphysics". Chicago, IL: S C Griggs and Company.
  • Morris, G. S. (1882). Metaphysics as a science. Chicago, IL: S C Griggs and Company.
  • Nakagomi, T. (2004). Quantum monadology and consciousness. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Noe, A., & Thompson, E. (2002). Vision and mind: Selected readings in the philosophy of perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Noordhof, P. (2003). Not old . . . but not that new either: Explicability, emergence, and the characterisation of materialism. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Panksepp, J. (1999). The periconscious substrates of consciousness: Affective states and the evolutionary origins of the self. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Paulsen, F., & Thilly, F. (1900). The freedom of the will. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Perlis, D. (1999). Consciousness as self-function. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Pessa, E. (2004). Quantum connectionism and the emergence of cognition. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Pettigrew, D. (2000). Peirce and Derrida: From sign to sign. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
  • Physicus. (1913). The argument from metaphysical teleology. London, England: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Company.
  • Pickering, J. (1999). The self is a semiotic process. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Plotnitsky, A. (2004). The unthinkable: Nonclassical theory, the unconscious mind and the quantum brain. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Polger, T. W. (2007). Some metaphysical anxieties of reductionism. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
  • Porter, N. (1871). Theories of intuitive knowledge. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Putnam, J. J. (1921). The necessity of metaphysics. Honolulu, HI: Hogarth Press.
  • Pylkkanen, P. (2004). Can quantum analogies help us to understand the process of thought? Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Radden, J. (1999). Pathologically divided minds, synchronic unity and models of self. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Raymont, P. (2003). Kim on closure, exclusion and nonreductive physicalism. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Rediger, J. (2005). Bipolar Disorder and Western Anosognosia. New York, NY: Haworth Press.
  • Ricord, E. (1840). Elements of the philosophy of mind, applied to the development of thought and feeling. New York, NY: John N Bogert.
  • Riese, W. (1950). Integrative action. New York, NY: Nervous and Mental Disease Monographs.
  • Robertson, G. C. (1894). The history of psychology. London, Great Britain: Williams and Norgate.
  • Robertson, G. C. (1894). The metaphysics of John Stuart Mill. London, Great Britain: Williams and Norgate.
  • Robertson, G. C., & Whittaker, T. (1894). Psychology in philosophic teaching. London, Great Britain: Williams and Norgate.
  • Robinson, D. N. (1993). William James on the mind and the body. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
  • Robinson, H. J. (1975). Renascent rationalism. Oxford, England: Macmillan.
  • Rosenberg, J. (1991). "Tractarian states" and folk-psychological explanation. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sass, L. A. (1999). Schizophrenia, self-consciousness, and the modern mind. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Searle, J. R. (1998). How to study consciousness scientifically. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Smith, T. V. (1934). The metaphysical implementation of conscience. New York, NY: Whittlesey House/McGraw-Hill Book Company.
  • Smyth, N. (1877). The feeling of dependence. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Takahashi, Y., & Jibu, M. (2004). Brain and Quantum Field Theory: Notes on monumental discussions presenting quantum field models of brain. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Tani, J. (1999). An interpretation of the "self" from the dynamical systems perspective: A constructivist approach. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Taylor, E. (2008). William James on pure experience and samadhi in Samkhya-Yoga. New Delhi, India: Cambridge University Press India/Foundation Books.
  • Taylor, E., & Sugg, J. G. (2008). Yoga psychology and the Samkhya metaphysic. New Delhi, India: Cambridge University Press India/Foundation Books.
  • Taylor, E. I. (1992). Psychology as a person-centered science: William James after 1890: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Titchener, E. B. (1906). The ultimate nature of mind. Mind and body. Basingstoke, Hampshire, England: Macmillan Education.
  • Valentine, E. R. (2000). Metaphysics: Kazdin, Alan E (Ed).
  • Vitiello, G. (2004). The dissipative brain. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Wallraff, C. F. (1961). Gestalt rejection of the unconscious and its metaphysical basis. Tuscon, AZ: The University of Arizona Press.
  • Wallraff, C. F. (1961). Philosophy as cosmic interpretation. Tuscon, AZ: The University of Arizona Press.
  • Wallraff, C. F. (1961). Sensory immediacy and its varieties. Tuscon, AZ: The University of Arizona Press.
  • Walter, S., & Heckmann, H.-D. (2003). Physicalism and mental causation: The metaphysics of mind and action. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Wilkes, K. V. (1999). "Gnothi Seayton" (know thyself). Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Williams, R. N. (1990). The metaphysic of things and discourse about them. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.
  • Wilson, R. A., & Craver, C. F. (2007). Realization: Metaphysical and Scientific Perspectives. Amsterdam, Netherlands: North Holland/Elsevier.
  • Winston, A. S. (2001). Cause into function: Ernst Mach and the reconstruction of explanation in psychology. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
  • Witmer, G. (2003). Multiple realizability and psychological laws: Evaluating Kim's challenge. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Wolf, S. (1987). Sanity and the metaphysics of responsibility. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Wolter, A. B. (1962). Concerning metaphysics. New York, NY: Thomas Nelson and Sons.


Papers[]

  • Alford, C. F. (2001). Reply to Michael Levine's 'See no evil, hear no evil, speak no evil: Psychiatry, psychoanalysis and evil.' Psychoanalytic Studies Vol 3(1) Mar 2001, 111-114.
  • Anderson, J. R. (2008). Asking baboons what they think: Evolutionary Psychology Vol 6(1) 2008, 64-66.
  • Antonelli, G. (1991). The prophet's dream: II: Giornale Storico di Psicologia Dinamica Vol 15(30) Jun 1991, 55-69.
  • Arlow, J. A. (1975). The structural hypothesis: Theoretical considerations: Psychoanalytic Quarterly Vol 44(4) 1975, 509-525.
  • Armstrong, A. C., Jr. (1895). Book review: Philosophy of Mind: An Essay in the Metaphysics of Psychology: Psychological Review Vol 2(3) May 1895, 299-303.
  • Atkins, K. (2008). Review of Controversies and subjectivity: Pragmatics & Cognition Vol 16(1) 2008, 193-196.
  • Auerswald, E. H. (1986). Family therapy as a movement: Epistemological barriers to ontological freedom: Journal of Strategic & Systemic Therapies Vol 5(4) Win 1986, 14-19.
  • Aurigemma, L. (2000). Jung and metaphysics: Giornale Storico di Psicologia Dinamica Vol 24(48) Jun 2000, 15-42.
  • Aydede, M. (2005). Pain: New essays on its nature and the methodology of its study. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Bakan, D. (2001). On the reality of the incorporeal intelligibles: A reflection on the metaphysics of psychology: Perceptual and Motor Skills Vol 93(2) Oct 2001, 531-540.
  • Baker, L. R. (1993). Metaphysics and mental causation. New York, NY: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.
  • Baker, L. R. (2007). Persons and other things. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Balbi, J. (1996). What is a person? Reflections on the domain of psychology from an ontological and postrationalist perspective: Journal of Constructivist Psychology Vol 9(4) Oct-Dec 1996, 249-261.
  • Baldwin, J. M. (1890). Handbook of psychology: Senses and intellect (second edition, revised). Ny: Henry Holt and Company.
  • Baldwin, J. M. (1903). Recent discussion in materialism. London, Great Britain: John C Nimmo.
  • Balz, A. G. A. (1941). Philosophy and psychology: Psychological Review Vol 48(6) Nov 1941, 530-551.
  • Barad, K. (2003). Posthumanist performativity: Toward an understanding of how matter comes to matter: Signs Vol 28(3) Spr 2003, 801-831.
  • Barber, J. F. (2005). Consciousness and Teleportation: 6th Swiss Biennial on Science, Technics + Aesthetics. Lucerne, Switzerland, January 22-23, 2005: Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 12(3) Mar 2005, 83-86.
  • Barendregt, M., & van Rappard, J. F. H. (2004). Reductionism revisited: On the role of reduction in psychology: Theory & Psychology Vol 14(4) Aug 2004, 453-474.
  • Barone, N. C. (1981). How foregone conclusions about the mind-body relation inhibit research: Psychological Reports Vol 49(3) Dec 1981, 812-814.
  • Bass, A. (1993). Psychopathology, metaphysics: American Imago Vol 50(2) Sum 1993, 197-225.
  • Bassols, A. T. (2004). Freedom of Will and Involuntary action: Acta Comportamentalia Vol 12(Monogr) 2004, 75-96.
  • Bateman, J. A. (1995). On the relationship between ontology construction and natural language: A socio-semiotic view: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 929-944.
  • Batty, A. M. (1908). Review of Attention Fatigue and the Concept of Infinity: Psychological Bulletin Vol 5(2) Feb 1908, 57.
  • Bauman, H. D. L. (2004). Audism: Exploring the Metaphysics of Oppression: Journal of Deaf Studies and Deaf Education Vol 9(2) Spr 2004, 239-246.
  • Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychology: Perspectives on Psychological Science Vol 3(1) Jan 2008, 14-19.
  • Baumgartner, E. (2005). Review of Die Ontologie Franz Brentanos: Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences Vol 41(1) Win 2005, 82-83.
  • Bawden, H. H. (1907). Review of Image, Idea and Meaning: Psychological Bulletin Vol 4(8) Aug 1907, 268-271.
  • Baxter, A. (1787). Dean Berkeley's scheme against the existence of matter, and a material world examined, and shown inconclusive. London, Great Britain: A Millar.
  • Baxter, A. (1787). That matter is not eternal and uncaused, nor the eternal effect of an external cause. London, Great Britain: A Millar.
  • Beasley, F. (1822). Of metaphysical science. Philadelphia, PA: S Potter and Co.
  • Beasley, F. (1822). Of our acquired perceptions, and the metaphysics of vision. Philadelphia, PA: S Potter and Co.
  • Beasley, F. (1822). The same subject continued. Philadelphia, PA: S Potter and Co.
  • Becchio, C., & Bertone, C. (2005). The ontology of neglect: Consciousness and Cognition: An International Journal Vol 14(3) Sep 2005, 483-494.
  • Beebe, J. (2004). Response to Wolfgang Giegerich's "The End of Meaning and the Birth of Man": Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(1) 2004, 95-98.
  • Beloff, J. (1989). Dualism: A parapsychological perspective. Charlottesville, VA: University of Virginia Press.
  • Benvenuto, S. (2003). Freud and Masochism: Journal of European Psychoanalysis No 16 2003, 57-80.
  • Benvenuto, S. (2005). Memory and desire: Psicoterapia e scienze umane Vol 39(4) 2005, 479-486.
  • Benzoni, F. J. (2007). Ecological ethics and the human soul: Aquinas, Whitehead, and the metaphysics of value. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Berg, A. (2004). Letters to the Editor: Astrid Berg, M.D: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(2) 2004, 65-66.
  • Bermudez, J. L. (1997). Reduction and the self: Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 4(5-6) 1997, 458-466.
  • Bermudez, J. L. (1999). Reduction and the self. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Berzonsky, M. D. (1993). The Quest for the Self: Soul, Illusion, or Dynamic Synthesis? : PsycCRITIQUES Vol 38 (9), Sep, 1993.
  • Bickhard, M. H. (1994). Rock, frogs, and the Cartesian gulf: Toward a naturalism of persons: New Ideas in Psychology Vol 12(3) Nov 1994, 267-276.
  • Bickhard, M. H. (2004). The Dynamic Emergence of Representation. Oxford, England: Elsevier Science Ltd.
  • Bickhard, M. H. (2008). Issues in process metaphysics: Ecological Psychology Vol 20(3) Jul 2008, 252-256.
  • Bickhard, M. H., & Christopher, J. C. (1994). The influence of early experience on personality development: New Ideas in Psychology Vol 12(3) Nov 1994, 229-252.
  • Bilu, Y., & Goodman, Y. C. (1997). What does the soul say? Metaphysical uses of facilitated communication in the Jewish ultraorthodox community: Ethos Vol 25(4) Dec 1997, 375-407.
  • Binet, A. (1896). Review of Du fondement de l'induction, suivi de psychologie et metaphysique: Psychological Review Vol 3(5) Sep 1896, 551-553.
  • Bjelland, A. G. (1987). Durational succession and proto-mental agency. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Harwood Academic Publishers.
  • Blachowicz, J. (1999). The dialogue of the soul with itself. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Blank, A. (2006). Review of Consciousness and Persons. Unity and Identity: Pragmatics & Cognition Vol 14(1) 2006, 188-192.
  • Bledsoe, A. T. (1845). Of Edwards' use of the term necessity. Philadelphia, PA: H Hooker.
  • Bledsoe, A. T. (1845). Of the maxim that every effect must have a cause. Philadelphia, PA: H Hooker.
  • Blight, J. G. (1979). Popper's Pedigree in the history of psychology: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 24 (11), Nov, 1979.
  • Bode, B. H. (1922). What is Psychology? : Psychological Review Vol 29(4) Jul 1922, 250-258.
  • Boersema, D. (2004). Metaphysics, mind, and the unity of science: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 627.
  • Bohm, D., & Welwood, J. (1980). Issues in physics, psychology and metaphysics: A conversation: Journal of Transpersonal Psychology Vol 12(1) 1980, 25-36.
  • Boldyreva, L. B., & Sotina, N. B. (2002). Superfluid vacuum as a basis for explanation of some phenomena of parapsychology: Journal of International Society of Life Information Science Vol 20(2) Sep 2002, 543-548.
  • Bonfatti, F., & Pazzi, L. (1995). Ontological foundations for state and identity within the object-oriented paradigm: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 891-906.
  • Bosanquet, B. (1892). Kant--The problem brought to a focus. New York, NY: Swan Sonnenschein & Co.
  • Bosanquet, B. (1911). The above theory of judgment in relation to 'absolutism'. New York, NY: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.
  • Bourdin, D. (2005). Logic, semiotics, pragmatism and metaphysics. A note on the theory of Charles Sanders Peirce: Revue Francaise de Psychanalyse Vol 69(3) Jun 2005, 733-747.
  • Boutroux, E. (1912). Metaphysical views. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • Bowen, F. (1849). Lecture I. The distinction between physical and metaphysical science. Boston, MA: Charles C Little and James Brown.
  • Bowen, F. (1849). Lecture III. The idea of self, or personal existence. Boston, MA: Charles C Little and James Brown.
  • Bowen, F. (1849). Lowell lectures on the application of metaphysical and ethical science to the evidences of religion. Boston, MA: Charles C Little and James Brown.
  • Bowen, F. (1880). John S. Mill's examination of Sir William Hamilton's philosophy--From the American Presbyterian Review for April and July, 1869. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Bowne, B. P. (1876). Principles of psychology. New York, NY: Nelson & Phillips.
  • Bowne, B. P. (1876). Summary and conclusion. New York, NY: Nelson & Phillips.
  • Bowne, B. P. (1908). Common sense, science, and philosophy. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Bowne, B. P. (1908). Personalism. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Bowne, B. P. (1908). The problem of knowledge. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Boyer, P. (1998). Cognitive tracks of cultural inheritance: How evolved intuitive ontology governs cultural transmission: American Anthropologist Vol 100(4) Dec 1998, 876-889.
  • Boyer, P. (2000). Natural epistemology or evolved metaphysics? Developmental evidence for early-developed, intuitive, category-specific, incomplete, and stubborn metaphysical presumptions: Philosophical Psychology Vol 13(3) Sep 2000, 277-297.
  • Bradie, M. (2001). The metaphysical foundation of Campbell's selectionist epistemology. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
  • Bradley, F. H. (1893). Appearance and reality: a metaphysical essay. New York, NY: Swan Sonnenschein & Co.
  • Bradley, F. H. (1893). Book I. Appearance. New York, NY: Swan Sonnenschein & Co.
  • Bradley, F. H. (1893). Book II. Reality. New York, NY: Swan Sonnenschein & Co.
  • Brender, M. (1959). A critique of Walters' position: Journal of Counseling Psychology Vol 6(2) Sum 1959, 163-165.
  • Brett, G. S. (1912). The psychology of Aristotle (I). London, United Kingdom: George Allen & Unwin.
  • Brinkmann, S. (2004). The topography of moral ecology: Theory & Psychology Vol 14(1) Feb 2004, 57-80.
  • Brinkmann, S. (2005). Psychology's facts and values: A perennial entanglement: Philosophical Psychology Vol 18(6) Dec 2005, 749-765.
  • Brodie, B. (1857). The second dialogue. New York, NY: G P Putnam & Co.
  • Brodie, B. C. (1862). The first dialogue. London, England: Longman, Green, Longman, and Roberts.
  • Brook, A. (1999). Unified consciousness and the self. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Brooke, R. (2000). Jung's recollection of the life-world. Florence, KY: Taylor & Frances/Routledge.
  • Brooks, D. (2000). How to solve the hard problem: A predictable inexplicability: Psyche: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research on Consciousness Vol 6(4) Feb 2000, No Pagination Specified.
  • Brown, J. W. (1998). Fundamentals of process neuropsychology: Brain and Cognition Vol 38(2) Nov 1998, 234-245.
  • Buckley, J. M. (1892). "Christian science" and "mind cure". Buckley, J. M. (1892). Faith-healing: Christian science and kindred phenomena.
  • Burton, A. (1824). Essays on some of the first principles of metaphysics, ethicks, and theology: Burton, Asa.
  • Butterworth, G. (1999). A developmental-ecological perspective on Strawson's "the self". Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Cairns, H. S. (1976). Recipe for a New Cognitive Psychology: Metaphysics, Neobehaviorism, and J. J. Gibson: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 21 (5), May, 1976.
  • Calderwood, H. (1888). The first cause. London, Great Britain: Macmillan and Co.
  • Calderwood, H. (1888). Metaphysical procedure. London, Great Britain: Macmillan and Co.
  • Calderwood, H. (1888). Relations of the moral governor to the problems of moral life. London, Great Britain: Macmillan and Co.
  • Calkins, M. W. (1905). Review of The Meaning of the Physical from the Point of View of the Functional Psychology: Psychological Bulletin Vol 2(5) May 1905, 174-175.
  • Calkins, M. W. (1907). Contemporary philosophical systems: The issue between pluralistic and monistic personalism. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Calkins, M. W. (1907). The persistent problems of philosophy: An introduction to metaphysics through the study of modern systems (2nd rev. ed.). New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Callieri, B. (1996). Anthropological aspects of encounters: Ourselves between psychoanalysis and metaphysics: Archivio di Psicologia, Neurologia e Psichiatria Vol 57(5-6) Sep-Dec 1996, 477-485.
  • Carnochan, P. G. M. (2006). Containers Without Lids: Psychoanalytic Dialogues Vol 16(3) May-Jun 2006, 341-362.
  • Carroll, S. (2004). Insignificance: Nature Vol 429(6987) May 2004, 27.
  • Cary, P. (2007). A brief history of the concept of free will: Issues that are and are not germane to legal reasoning: Behavioral Sciences & the Law Vol 25(2) 2007, 165-181.
  • Charles, C. (1992). A horse is a horse: Love and sex in Plato's Phaedrus: Literature and Psychology Vol 38(3) 1992, 47-70.
  • Chartier, D. A. (2008). Melancholy: From psychiatry to metaphysics: L'Evolution Psychiatrique Vol 73(1) Jan 2008, 69-78.
  • Chase, R. (1979). The mentalist hypothesis and invertebrate neurobiology: Perspectives in Biology and Medicine Vol 23(1) Fal 1979, 103-117.
  • Chen, L., Shadbolt, N. R., Tao, F., Goble, C., Puleston, C., & Cox, S. J. (2005). Semantics-Assisted Problem Solving on the Semantic Grid: Computational Intelligence Vol 21(2) May 2005, 157-176.
  • Chessick, R. D. (1982). Metaphysics or autistic reverie? : Contemporary Psychoanalysis Vol 18(1) Jan 1982, 160-172.
  • Chnaiderman, M. (1995). The question of death in the contemporary world: Theater, photography and psychoanalysis: Percurso Revista de Psicanalise Vol 8(15)[2] 1995, 89-93.
  • Choquette, K. A. (2007). Process, quantum coherence, and the stream of consciousness: Journal of Mind and Behavior Vol 28(3-4) Sum-Aut 2007, 203-232.
  • Clarke, C. (2005). Being and Field Theory: Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 12(4-5) Apr-May 2005, 135-139.
  • Clarke, S. (2004). Ontological disunity and a realism worth having: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 628-629.
  • Clifford, W. K., Stephen, L., & Pollock, F. (1886). Body and mind. London, Great Britain: Macmillan and Co.
  • Clifford, W. K., Stephen, L., & Pollock, F. (1886). The first and the last catastrophe. London, Great Britain: Macmillan and Co.
  • Clifford, W. K., Stephen, L., & Pollock, F. (1886). On the nature of things-in-themselves. London, Great Britain: Macmillan and Co.
  • Cocchiarella, N. B. (1995). Knowledge representation in conceptual realism: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 697-721.
  • Cohen, J. (1990). Face-figure-mask: Psychologie Medicale Vol 22(10) Oct 1990, 1019-1025.
  • Coleman, S. (2007). Review of A place for consciousness and Ignorance and imagination: Philosophical Psychology Vol 20(6) Dec 2007, 826-833.
  • Collard-Bovy, O. (2006). Empirical study of Rawls' political philosphy: Impartiality vs. metaphysics: Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology Vol 26(1-2) 2006, 95-119.
  • Collier, J. (2004). Reduction, supervenience, and physical emergence: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 629-630.
  • Combe, G. (1835). On natural laws. Edinburgh, Great Britain: John Anderson Jr.
  • Connolly, A. (2004). Letters to the Editor: Angela Connolly, D.ssa: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(2) 2004, 66.
  • Conte, J. L. (1891). The relation of Louis Agassiz to the theory of evolution. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Cooper, A. M. (1957). System and metasystem: American Psychologist Vol 12(8) Aug 1957, 521-522.
  • Cooper, W. (2003). William James's Moral Theory: Journal of Moral Education Vol 32(4) Dec 2003, 411-422.
  • Corcoran, K. (2005). The constitution view of persons. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
  • Cousin, M. V., & Wight, O. W. (1852). Lecture XIV. Sensualistic school in the eighteenth century. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Cousin, M. V., & Wight, O. W. (1852). Lecture XV. Locke. His life. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Crombie, A. D. (1964). Early concepts of the senses and the mind: Scientific American 210(5) 1964, 108-116.
  • Culler, E. (1926). Review of Die physischen gestalten in ruhe und im stationaren zustand: Psychological Bulletin Vol 23(6) Jun 1926, 317-323.
  • Curran, R. (2004). Letters to the Editor: Ron Curran, Ph.D: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(2) 2004, 64-65.
  • Damian, D. E. H., Jonker, C. M., Treur, J., & Wijngaards, N. J. E. (2005). Integration of behavioural requirements specification within compositional knowledge engineering: Knowledge-Based Systems Vol 18(7) Nov 2005, 353-365.
  • Dansby, B. A. (2005). Review of Lotus birth and Lotus birth: The water birth of the Malcolm twins: Journal of Prenatal & Perinatal Psychology & Health Vol 20(2) Win 2005, 180-182.
  • Dansby, B. A. (2006). Review of Lotus Birth; and Lotus Birth: The Water Birth of the Malcolm Twins: Journal of Prenatal & Perinatal Psychology & Health Vol 21(1) Fal 2006, 93-96.
  • Daubner, E. V., & Daubner, E. S. (1972). The counselor as metaphysician: Personnel & Guidance Journal Vol 50(5) Jan 1972, 363-370.
  • David, H. P. (1969). Review of Die Ausserpsychologischen Voraussetzungen der Tiefenpsychologie. (Metaphysical Assumptions of Depth Psychology.): PsycCRITIQUES Vol 14 (10), Oct, 1969.
  • David, J. (2004). Letters to the Editor: Julian David, M.A: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(2) 2004, 61-62.
  • Davies, J. B. (2004). Bring on the physics revolution: The Psychologist Vol 17(12) Dec 2004, No Pagination Specified.
  • Davis, R. C. (1936). American psychology, 1800-1885: Psychological Review Vol 43(6) Nov 1936, 471-493.
  • Dayan, M. (1990). Death denial and the passage of time: Psychanalyse a l'Universite Vol 15(57) Jan 1990, 3-22.
  • de Beauregard, O. C. (1987). Bergson's duration and quantal spacetime non-separability. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Harwood Academic Publishers.
  • de Fontenay, E. (1990). A responsibility without a subject: Psychanalystes Vol 37 1990, 19-28.
  • de Lisondo, A. B. D. (2004). In the culture of emptiness, pathologies from the emptiness: Revista Brasileira de Psicanalise Vol 38(2) 2004, 335-358.
  • De Spinoza, B., & Fullerton, G. S. (1894). The philosophy of Spinoza, as contained in the first, second, and fifth parts of the "Ethics," and in extracts from the third and fourth (2nd ed., enlarged). New York, NY: Henry Holt and Co.
  • De Wulf, M. (1922). Individualism and social philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • De Wulf, M. (1922). Philosophy and civilization in the Middle Ages. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • De Wulf, M. (1922). A pluralistic conception of the world. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Dearborn, G. V. N. (1927). The "two-love question;" an example of unconscious erotic symbolism: The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology Vol 22(1) Apr 1927, 62-66.
  • Deikman, A. (1999). "I" = awareness. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Del Giudice, E. (2004). The psycho-emotional-physical unity of living organisms as an outcome of quantum physics. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Delacroix, H. (1912). Review of L'Experience Mystique et l'Activite Subconsciente: Psychological Bulletin Vol 9(12) Dec 1912, 470-472.
  • Dell, P. F. (1985). Understanding Bateson and Maturana: Toward a biological foundation for the social sciences: Journal of Marital & Family Therapy Vol 11(1) Jan 1985, 1-20.
  • DeRobertis, E., & Iuculano, J. (2005). Metaphysics and Psychology: A Problem of the Personal: Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology Vol 25(2) Fal 2005, 238-256.
  • Desideri, F. (2004). The self-transcendence of consciousness towards its models. Consciousness as noumenal emergence: Some philosophical remarks on the Quantum Field Theory model of Giuseppe Vitiello. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Dewey, J. (1888). Material phenomena and their reality. Chicago, IL: S C Griggs and Company.
  • Dewey, J. (1888). Matter and its relation to spirit. Chicago, IL: S C Griggs and Company.
  • Dewey, J. (1896). The metaphysical method in ethics: Psychological Review Vol 3(2) Mar 1896, 181-188.
  • Diamond, S. (1978). How chicks will stray! : PsycCRITIQUES Vol 23 (10), Oct, 1978.
  • Dietzgen, J. (1906). The light of cognition. Chicago, IL: Charles H Kerr & Company.
  • Dilworth, C. (2006). The metaphysics of science: An account of modern science in terms of principles, laws and theories (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Springer Science + Business Media.
  • Dolev, Y. (2007). Time and realism: Metaphysical and antimetaphysical perspectives. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Dolling, J. (1995). Ontological domains, semantic sorts and systematic ambiguity: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 785-807.
  • Dueck, A., & Becker, B. (2006). The Roots of Kekes? : PsycCRITIQUES Vol 51 (4), 2006.
  • Dueck, A. L. (2004). Introduction: Journal of Psychology & Theology Vol 32(3) Fal 2004, 163-166.
  • Duncan, G. M. (1890). Letter from Leibnitz to Arnauld in which he states his personal views on metaphysics and physics, 1690. New Haven, CT: Tuttle, Morehouse & Taylor.
  • Duncan, G. M. (1890). On the Cartesian demonstration of the existence of God, 1700-1701. New Haven, CT: Tuttle, Morehouse & Taylor.
  • Duncan, G. M. (1890). On the reform of metaphysics and of the notion of substance, 1694. New Haven, CT: Tuttle, Morehouse & Taylor.
  • Duncan, G. M. (1890). On the ultimate origin of things, 1697. New Haven, CT: Tuttle, Morehouse & Taylor.
  • Duncan, G. M. (1908). Review of The Persistent Problems of Philosophy: An Introduction to Metaphysics Through the Study of Modern Systems: Psychological Bulletin Vol 5(5) May 1908, 153-157.
  • Eagle, M. N. (1984). Freud, Darwin, and the End of Metaphysics: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 29 (3), Mar, 1984.
  • Eaton, R. M. (1925). The metaphysics of knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Eberl, J. T. (2005). A Thomistic Understanding of Human Death: Bioethics Vol 19(1) Feb 2005, 29-48.
  • Edey, M. (1999). Subject and object. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Ehrlich, K. (2005). Review of The Biology of Belief: Unleashing the Power of Consciousness, Matter, & Miracles: Journal of Prenatal & Perinatal Psychology & Health Vol 20(1) Fal 2005, 88-91.
  • Eidlin, F. (1979). Weimer's "Popper legend" again: Avoiding the issues: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 24 (2), Feb, 1979.
  • Elder, C. L. (2007). On the place of artifacts in ontology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Eliasmith, C. (2007). Computational Neuroscience. Amsterdam, Netherlands: North Holland/Elsevier.
  • Ellens, J. H. (2005). Review of Reforming Theological Anthropology after the Philosophical Turn to Relationality: Journal of Psychology and Christianity Vol 24(2) Sum 2005, 180-181.
  • Elliot, H. (1917). Metaphysics and religion. Ny: Henry Holt and Company.
  • Elliot, H. (1919). The fallacy of vitalism. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • Elliot, H. (1919). The universe as a whole. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • Ellis, R. D. (2004). Review of Quantum closures and disclosures: Thinking-together postphenomenology and quantum brain dynamics: Journal of Phenomenological Psychology Vol 35(1) Spr 2004, 142-146.
  • English, H. B. (1927). Review of The case for and against psychic belief: Journal of Applied Psychology Vol 11(3) Jun 1927, 243-246.
  • English, H. B. (1933). The ghostly tradition and the descriptive categories of psychology: Psychological Review Vol 40(6) Nov 1933, 498-513.
  • Epstein, M. (2007). Methods of madness and madness as a method. Toronto, ON, Canada: University of Toronto Press.
  • Esbjorn-Hargens, S. (2006). A Integral Research: A Multi-Method Approach to Investigating Phenomena: Constructivism in the Human Sciences Vol 11(1-2) 2006, 79-107.
  • Eucken, R., & Phelps, M. S. (1880). Immanent (cosmic). New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Eucken, R., & Phelps, M. S. (1880). Monism--Dualism. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Eugene, M. (2004). Letters to the Editor: Eugene Monick, M.Div., Ph.D: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(2) 2004, 66.
  • Evans, W. F. (1885). The Kabalistic and Messianic method of healing, and the one practised by Jesus the Christ. Boston, MA: H H Carter & Karrick Publishers.
  • Fales, E. (2007). Naturalism and physicalism. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Falk, J. L. (1953). The role of cultural metaphysics in psychological theory: Canadian Journal of Psychology/Revue canadienne de psychologie Vol 7(1) Mar 1953, 34-39.
  • Farah, M. J. (2005). Reply to Jedlicka: Neuroethics, reductionism and dualism: Trends in Cognitive Sciences Vol 9(4) Apr 2005, 173.
  • Faulconer, J. E. (1995). Newton, science, and causation: Journal of Mind and Behavior Vol 16(1) Win 1995, 77-86.
  • Fechner, G. T., & Wadsworth, M. C. (1904). The little book of life after death. New York, NY: Little, Brown and Co.
  • Feder, F. (1996). Violence and adolescence: From the violence of life on the skids to a metapsychological reflection about violence during adolescence: Psychologie Clinique et Projective Vol 2(1) 1996, 63-91.
  • Fernandez-Breis, J. T., & Martinez-Bejar, R. (2002). A cooperative framework for integrating ontologies: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 56(6) Jun 2002, 665-720.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Institutes of metaphysic: The theory of knowing and being. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition I. The primary law or condition of all knowledge. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition I. The three alternatives as to absolute existence. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition I. What ignorance is. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition II. A premiss by which the third alternative is eliminated. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition II. Ignorance remediable. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition II. The object of all knowledge. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition III. A premiss by which the third alternative is eliminated. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition III. The inseparability of the objective and the subjective. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition III. What there can be ignorance of. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition IV. Eliminates the third alternative. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition IV. Ignorance of objects per se. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition IV. Matter per se. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition IX. The ego per se. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition IX. The origin of knowledge. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition V. Ignorance of matter per se. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition V. Matter and its qualities per se. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition V. The remaining alternatives. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition VI. Ignorance of the universal and particular. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition VI. The universal and the particular in cognition. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition VI. What absolute existence is not. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition VII. Ignorance of the ego per se. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition VII. What absolute existence is not. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition VII. What the universal and the particular in cognition are. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition VIII. The ego in cognition. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition VIII. The object of all ignorance. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition VIII. What absolute existence is not. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition X. Sense and intellect. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition X. What absolute existence is. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XI. Presentation and representation. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XI. What absolute existence is necessary. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XII. Matter per se again. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XIII. The independent universe in thought. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XIV. The phenomenal in cognition. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XIX. What the relative in cognition is. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XV. What the phenomenal cognition is. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XVI. The substantial in cognition. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XVII. What the substantial in cognition is. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XVIII. The relative in cognition. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XX. The absolute in cognition. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XXI. What the absolute in cognition is. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Ferrier, J. F. (1854). Proposition XXII. The contingent conditions of knowledge. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Fidelman, U. (1994). The brain, ontology, and freedom of the mind: Journal of Structural Learning Vol 12(2) Apr 1994, 71-85.
  • Fischer, R. (1977). The making of reality: Journal of Altered States of Consciousness Vol 3(4) 1977-1978, 371-389.
  • Fisher, W. P., Jr. (2003). Mathematics, measurement, metaphor and metaphysics I: Implications for method in postmodern science: Theory & Psychology Vol 13(6) Dec 2003, 753-790.
  • Fisher, W. P., Jr. (2003). Mathematics, measurement, metaphor and metaphysics II: Accounting for Galileo's 'fateful omission': Theory & Psychology Vol 13(6) Dec 2003, 791-828.
  • Fiske, J. (1884). The dawning of consciousness. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Fiske, J. (1884). The destiny of man, viewed in the light of his origin (14th ed.). Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Fiske, J. (1884). Man's place in nature, as affected by the Copernican theory. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Fiss, H. (1980). Review of The dream and the underworld: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 25 (6), Jun, 1980.
  • Flanagan, O. J. (1980). Skinnerian metaphysics and the problem of operationism: Behaviorism Vol 8(1) Spr 1980, 1-13.
  • Fleischmann, M. (2004). Searching for the biophysics of an elementary system. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Fletcher, G. J. O. (1992). The Social Construction of Our Bodies: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 37 (11), Nov, 1992.
  • Flinn, M. V. (2006). Evolution and ontogeny of stress response to social challenges in the human child: Developmental Review Vol 26(2) Jun 2006, 138-174.
  • Fogel, P. H. (1904). Metaphysical Elements in Sociology. I: American Journal of Sociology X 1904, 354-381.
  • Forman, R. K. C. (1999). What does mysticism have to teach us about consciousness? Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Fox, R. A. (2006). On Metaphysics and Nationality: The Rival Enlightenments of Kant and Herder: American Behavioral Scientist Vol 49(5) Jan 2006, 716-732.
  • Franck, G. (2004). Mental presence and the temporal present. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Frank, A. W. (1987). Review of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche: Symbolic Interaction Vol 10(2) Nov 1987, 296-306.
  • Frank, D. A. (1997). The New Rhetoric, Judaism, and post-Enlightenment thought: The cultural origins of Perelmanian philosophy: Quarterly Journal of Speech Vol 83(3) Aug 1997, 311-331.
  • Frank, P. (1957). Metaphysical Interpretations of Relativistic Physics. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall/Pearson Education.
  • Frank, P. (1957). Metaphysical Interpretations of the Atomic World. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall/Pearson Education.
  • Frenkel-Brunswik, E. (1943). Review of Beyond psychology: The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology Vol 38(1) Jan 1943, 123-124.
  • Frothingham, O. B. (1876). Beginnings in Germany. New York, NY: G P Putnam's Sons.
  • Frothingham, O. B. (1876). Transcendentalism in Germany. New York, NY: G P Putnam's Sons.
  • Fulford, K. W. M., & Sadler, J. Z. (2002). Imaging the soul: Current Opinion in Psychiatry Vol 15(5) Sep 2002, 515-518.
  • Gallagher, S., & Marcel, A. J. (1999). The self in contextualized action. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Gamertsfelder, W. S. (1928). Review of Philosophy: Journal of Applied Psychology Vol 12(2) Apr 1928, 252-254.
  • Gantheret, F. (1988). Discussion of P. Luquet's report: Revue Francaise de Psychanalyse Vol 52(2) Mar-Apr 1988, 369-382.
  • Gardiner, H. N. (1896). Review of Zur Psychologie der Metaphysik: Psychological Review Vol 3(5) Sep 1896, 586-587.
  • Gardiner, H. N. (1897). Review of Causal-Nexus zivischen Leib und Seele und die daraus resultierenden psychophysischen Phanomene: Psychological Review Vol 4(1) Jan 1897, 90.
  • Gardiner, H. N. (1902). Review of Les Dilemmes de la Metaphysique Pure: Psychological Review Vol 9(1) Jan 1902, 80-82.
  • Gardiner, H. N. (1903). Review of Histoire et solution des problemes metaphysiques: Psychological Review Vol 10(3) May 1903, 320-322.
  • Gardiner, H. N., & Tosti, G. (1900). Psychological literature: Psychological Review Vol 7(3) May 1900, 289-295.
  • Garofoli, F. (1999). Between one and nobody..."I would prefer not to." Giornale Storico di Psicologia Dinamica Vol 23(45) Jan 1999, 119-129.
  • Garver, E. (2006). Confronting Aristotle's ethics: Ancient and modern morality. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • Gay, V. P. (1989). Philosophy, psychoanalysis, and the problem of change: Psychoanalytic Inquiry Vol 9(1) 1989, 26-44.
  • Gay, V. P. (1991). Toward the Unification of Psychology and Philosophy: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 36 (7), Jul, 1991.
  • Gedo, J. E. (1979). Theories of object relations: A metapsychological assessment: Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association Vol 27(2) 1979, 361-373.
  • Gersch, I., Dowling, F., Panagiotaki, G., & Potton, A. (2008). Listening to children's views of spiritual and metaphysical concepts: A new dimension to educational psychology practice? : Educational Psychology in Practice Vol 24(3) Sep 2008, 225-236.
  • Gibbs, R. W., Jr. (2008). Images schemas in conceptual development: What happened to the body? : Philosophical Psychology Vol 21(2) Apr 2008, 231-239.
  • Giegerich, W. (2004). The End of Meaning and the Birth of Man: An Essay about the State Reached in the History of Consciousness and an Analysis of C. G. Jung's Psychology Project: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(1) 2004, 1-65.
  • Giegerich, W. (2004). Response to the Responses by Mogenson, Miller, Beebe, and Pulver: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(1) 2004, 107-124.
  • Gillibert, J. (1985). "Translating metaphysics into metapsychology..." Revue Francaise de Psychanalyse Vol 49(5) Sep-Oct 1985, 1331-1343.
  • Glover, E. (1966). Metapsychology or metaphysics: A psychoanalytic essay: Psychoanalytic Quarterly 35(2) 1966, 173-190.
  • Goldenberg, M. J. (2007). The problem of exclusion in feminist theory and politics: A metaphysical investigation into constructing a category of 'woman': Journal of Gender Studies Vol 16(2) 2007, 139-153.
  • Golomb, J. (1978). Freud's Spinoza: A reconstruction: Israel Annals of Psychiatry & Related Disciplines Vol 16(4) Dec 1978, 275-288.
  • Good, I. J. (1964). Quantum mechanics and Yoga: Research Journal of Philosophy & Social Sciences 1(1) 1964, 84-91.
  • Good, J. M. (1837). Series III. Nature of the mind: Its general faculties and furniture. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Goodman, L. E. (1987). Determinism and freedom in Spinoza, Maimonides, and Aristotle: A retrospective study. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Goodson, F. E. (1963). Views of Science. Microscopic and Very Otherwise: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 8 (3), Mar, 1963.
  • Gore, C. (1902). Editor's preface. Chicago, IL: Open Court Publishing Co.
  • Grandy, D. A. (1996). A Heideggerian approach to human understanding: Genetic, Social, and General Psychology Monographs Vol 122(1) Feb 1996, 5-20.
  • Grandy, R. E. (2007). Artifacts: Parts and principles. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Gray, M. T. (2004). Philosophical Inquiry in Nursing: An Argument for Radical Empiricism as a Philosophical Framework for the Phenomenology of Addiction: Qualitative Health Research Vol 14(8) Oct 2004, 1151-1164.
  • Green, C. D. (1998). The thoroughly modern Aristotle: Was he really a functionalist? : History of Psychology Vol 1(1) Feb 1998, 8-20.
  • Groddeck, G. (1976). The book of the it. Oxford, England: International U Press.
  • Gruber, T. R. (1995). Toward principles for the design of ontologies used for knowledge sharing: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 907-928.
  • Guareschi, P. (1992). Presumptions for a critique of psychosocial theories: PSICO Vol 23(1) Jan-Jun 1992, 97-102.
  • Guareschi, P. A. (2003). Metaphysical and Epistemological Assumptions in the Research: Psicologia: Reflexao e Critica Vol 16(2) 2003, 245-255.
  • Guarino, N. (1995). Formal ontology, conceptual analysis and knowledge representation: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 625-640.
  • Guba, E. G., & Lincoln, Y. S. (1994). Competing paradigms in qualitative research. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, Inc.
  • Guiderdoni, B. (2006). Modern Cosmology and the Quest for Meaning: A Dialogue on the Road to Knowledge. West Conshohocken, PA: Templeton Foundation Press.
  • Haanel, C. F. (1924). Metaphysics. St. Louis, MO: Charles F Haanel.
  • Hacker, P. M. S. (2007). Human nature: The categorial framework. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
  • Haeckel, E., & McCabe, J. (1900). The evolution of the world. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Haeckel, E., & McCabe, J. (1900). The nature of the problem. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Haeckel, E., & McCabe, J. (1904). The value of life. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Haldane, R. B. (1905). Lecture I. New York, NY: E P Dutton and Company.
  • Haldane, R. B. (1905). Lecture II. New York, NY: E P Dutton and Company.
  • Haldane, R. B. (1905). Lecture III. New York, NY: E P Dutton and Company.
  • Haldane, R. B. (1905). Lecture IV. New York, NY: E P Dutton and Company.
  • Haldane, R. B. (1905). Lecture V. New York, NY: E P Dutton and Company.
  • Haldane, R. B. (1905). Lecture VI. New York, NY: E P Dutton and Company.
  • Haldane, R. B. (1905). The pathway to reality, Stage the second, being the Gifford lectures delivered in the University of St. Andrews in the session 1903-1904. New York, NY: E P Dutton and Company.
  • Halifax-Grof, J. (1976). Convergence of ancient and indigenous healing procedures with recent innovations in therapy: Multidisciplinary Research Vol 4(1) Apr 1976, 120-142.
  • Hall, E. W. (1942). Some dangers in the use of symbolic logic in psychology: Psychological Review Vol 49(2) Mar 1942, 142-169.
  • Hall, M. E. L. (2004). God as a cause or error?: Academic psychology as a Christian vocation: Journal of Psychology & Theology Vol 32(3) Fal 2004, 200-209.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1859). Lecture XVI. Consciousness--Violations of its authority. Boston, MA: Gould and Lincoln.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1859). Lectures on metaphysics and logic, Vol 1: Metaphysics. Boston, MA: Gould and Lincoln.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1863). Lectures on metaphysics and logic, Vol 1: Metaphysics. Boston, MA: Gould and Lincoln.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1866). Lecture XXX. Modified stoicheiology. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1866). Lectures on logic (Vol 2, 2nd ed. rev.). Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1866). Lectures on metaphysics and logic, Vol 3. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture II: Philosophy--Its absolute utility. (B) objective. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XL: The regulative faculty--Law of the conditioned in its applications--Causality. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XLI: Second great class of mental phenomena--The feelings: Their character and relation to the cognitions and conations. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XLII: The feelings--Theory of pleasure and pain. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XLIII: The feelings--Historical account of theories of pleasure and pain. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XLIV: The feelings--Application of the theory of pleasure and pain to the phaenomena. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XLV: The feelings--Their classes. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XLVI: The feelings--Their classes--The beautiful and sublime. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XX: Distribution of the special cognitive faculties. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXI: The presentative faculty--I. Perception--Reid's historical view of the theories of perception. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXII: The presentative faculty--I. Perception--Reid's historical view of the theories of perception. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXIII: The presentative faculty--I. Perception--Was Reid a natural realist? Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXIV: The presentative faculty--I. Perception--The distinction of perception proper from sensation proper. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXIX: The presentative faculty--II. Self-consciousness. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXV: The presentative faculty--I. Perception--Objections to the doctrine of realism. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXVI: The presentative faculty--I. Perception--The representative hypothesis. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXVII: The presentative faculty--I. Perception--General questions in relation to the senses. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXVIII: The presentative faculty--I. Perception-- Relation of sight and touch to extension. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXX: The conservative faculty--Memory proper. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXXI: The reproductive faculty--Laws of association. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXXII: The reproductive faculty--Laws of association--Suggestion--Reminiscence. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXXIII: The representative faculty--Imagination. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXXIV: The elaborative faculty--Classification--Abstraction. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXXIX: The regulative faculty--Law of the conditioned in its applications--Causality. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXXV: The elaborative faculty--Generalisation, nominalism, and conceptualism. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXXVI: The elaborative faculty--Generalisation--The primum cognitum. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXXVII: The elaborative faculty--Judgment and reasoning. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lecture XXXVIII: The regulative faculty. Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lectures on metaphysics (Vol 1, 4th ed.). Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hamilton, W., Mansel, H. L., & Veitch, J. (1869). Lectures on metaphysics (Vol 2, 4th ed.). Edinburgh, Great Britain: William Blackwood and Sons.
  • Hanly, C. (1995). Some comments on psychic reality: Revista de Psicoanalisis Vol 52(3) Jul-Sep 1995, 799-804.
  • Hanna, F. J., & Shank, G. (1995). The specter of metaphysics in counseling research and practice: The qualitative challenge: Journal of Counseling & Development Vol 74(1) Sep-Oct 1995, 53-59.
  • Hansen, G. P. (2002). Review of Quantum Leaps in the Wrong Direction: Journal of Parapsychology Vol 66(3) Sep 2002, 321-324.
  • Hare, B. (2008). Review of Baboon metaphysics: The evolution of a social mind: Animal Behaviour Vol 76(1) Jul 2008, 253-255.
  • Harre, R. (1991). Metaphysics and methodology. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
  • Harrington, A. (2007). Habermas's theological turn? : Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour Vol 37(1) Mar 2007, 45-61.
  • Harris, J. (1775). Chapter XVII. London, Great Britain: John Nourse.
  • Harris, P. L. (2000). On not falling down to earth: Children's metaphysical questions. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hartshorne, C. (1987). Bergson's aesthetic creationism compared to Whitehead's. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Harwood Academic Publishers.
  • Harvey, I. E. (1987). Schizophrenia and metaphysics: Analyzing the DSM-III. New York, NY: New York University Press.
  • Hathaway, W. L. (2004). Expanding horizons for Christians in psychology: Journal of Psychology & Theology Vol 32(3) Fal 2004, 210-220.
  • Haug, D. (2004). Aristotle's kinesis/energeia-test and the semantics of the Greek perfect: Linguistics Vol 42(2) 2004, 387-418.
  • Helminiak, D. A. (2005). A Down-to-Earth Approach to the Psychology of Spirituality a Century After James's Varieties: The Humanistic Psychologist Vol 33(2) 2005, 69-86.
  • Hershfield, J. (2002). A note on the possibility of silicon brains and fading qualia: Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 9(7) Jul 2002, 25-31.
  • Hibben, J. G. (1895). Review of A Study of Ethical Principles: Psychological Review Vol 2(1) Jan 1895, 75-76.
  • Hibben, J. G. (1900). Review of A Theory of Reality. An Essay in Metaphysical System Upon the Basis of Human Cognitive Experience: Psychological Review Vol 7(1) Jan 1900, 70-74.
  • Hibbert, S. (2007). 'The varieties of effects resulting from such morbific causes as are capable of rendering more vivid the feelings of the mind.' History of Psychiatry Vol 18(1) Mar 2007, 106-121.
  • Hillman, J. (2003). A Note for Stanton Marlan: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 5(2) 2003, 101-103.
  • Hobbs, J. R. (1995). Sketch of an ontology underlying the way we talk about the world: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 819-830.
  • Hodder, A. L. (1894). Review of Appearance and Reality: A Metaphysical Essay: Psychological Review Vol 1(3) May 1894, 307-311.
  • Hodes, S. E. (2008). Meta-physician on call for better health: Metaphysics and medicine for mind, body and spirit. Westport, CT: Praeger Publishers/Greenwood Publishing Group.
  • Hodge, C. W. (1895). Review of Monism as Connecting Religion and Science: Psychological Review Vol 2(6) Nov 1895, 611-612.
  • Hodge, C. W. (1895). Review of The Integration of Mind: Psychological Review Vol 2(6) Nov 1895, 615-616.
  • Hodgson, S. H. (1898). The metaphysic of experience, in four books: Vol 4, containing book 3, chapter 6 and last, The foundations of ethic, and book 4, The real universe. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • Hoffman, W. C. (1999). Dialectic--A universal for consciousness? : New Ideas in Psychology Vol 17(3) Dec 1999, 251-269.
  • Holt, D. (1975). Projection, presence, profession: Spring 1975, 130-144.
  • Hopkins, M. (1887). The place of man. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Howard, J. A. (1979). Person-situation interaction models: Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin Vol 5(2) Apr 1979, 191-195.
  • Howe, L. E. (2006). Enchantment, weak ontologies, and administrative ethics: Administration & Society Vol 38(4) Sep 2006, 422-446.
  • Howison, G. H. (1905). The limits of evolution and other essays: Illustrating the metaphysical theory of personal idealism (2nd ed., rev. and enlarged). New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hull, R. T. (1973). On taking causal criteria to be ontologically significant: Behaviorism Vol 1(2) Sum 1973, 65-76.
  • Hurley, T. J., III. (1993). Facilitating the study of consciousness: Emerging themes on the frontiers of science. Westport, CT: Praeger Publishers/Greenwood Publishing Group.
  • Hut, P., & van Fraassen, B. (1997). Elements of reality: A dialogue: Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 4(2) 1997, 167-180.
  • Hutto, D. D. (2006). Both Bradley and biology: Reply to Rudd. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Hutto, D. D. (2006). Impossible problems and careful expositions: Reply to Myin and De Nul. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Huxley, T. H. (1873). On the origin of species: or, The causes of the phenomena of organic nature: A course of six lectures to working men. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Huxley, T. H. (1882). On sensation and the unity of structure of the sensiferous organs. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Huxley, T. H. (1894). Bishop Berkeley on the metaphysics of sensation. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Huxley, T. H. (1894). Hume: With helps to the study of Berkeley, essays. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hyslop, J. H. (1905). The criteria of truth. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hyslop, J. H. (1905). The existence of God. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hyslop, J. H. (1905). General problems of science and philosophy. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hyslop, J. H. (1905). Metaphysical theories. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hyslop, J. H. (1905). Problems of philosophy or principles of epistemology and metaphysics. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hyslop, J. H. (1905). Spiritualism. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Iuculano, J., & Abaunza, G. (2006). The relevance of the metaphysics of Ortega y Gasset for psychology: Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology Vol 26(1-2) 2006, 189-204.
  • Jackson, F. (2003). David Kellogg Lewis: Philosopher and philosopher of mind: Mind & Language Vol 18(3) Jun 2003, 281-285.
  • Jacob, P. (2008). The scope and limits of enactive approaches to visual experience: Perception Vol 37(3) 2008, 446-461.
  • Jeanneau, A. (1988). Early manifestations of significance: Revue Francaise de Psychanalyse Vol 52(2) Mar-Apr 1988, 447-451.
  • Jedlicka, P. (2005). Neuroethics, reductionism and dualism: Trends in Cognitive Sciences Vol 9(4) Apr 2005, 172.
  • Johnson, A. (2005). Caught by Our Dangling Paradigms: How Our Metaphysical Assumptions Influence Gifted Education: Journal of Secondary Gifted Education Vol 16(2-3) Win-Spr 2005, 67-73.
  • Johnston, J. S. (2004). Authority, Inquiry, and Education: A Response to Dewey's Critics: Educational Studies: Journal of the American Educational Studies Association Vol 35(3) Jun 2004, 230-247.
  • Jouffroy, & Channing, W. H. (1848). Lecture VI. System of pantheism. Boston, MA: James Munroe and Company.
  • Jowett, B. (1901). The Republic. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Judd, C. H. (1908). Review of Pragmatism. A New Name for some Old Ways of Thinking: Psychological Bulletin Vol 5(5) May 1908, 157-162.
  • Kaidesoja, T. (2007). Exploring the concept of causal power in a critical realist tradition: Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour Vol 37(1) Mar 2007, 63-87.
  • Kalish, C. W., & Lawson, C. A. (2002). Children Think the Darndest Things: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 47 (4), Aug, 2002.
  • Kantor, J. R. (1975). Psychology, physics, and metaphysics: Revista Mexicana de Analisis de la Conducta Vol 1(1) Jan 1975, 31-38.
  • Kasuba, A. (1998). The physics of metaphysics: Personal musings: Journal of Mind and Behavior Vol 19(1) Win 1998, 65-90.
  • Katzko, M. W. (2006). The Re-emergence of Whitehead's Process Metaphysics: Theory & Psychology Vol 16(1) Feb 2006, 134-136.
  • Katzko, M. W. (2008). Pruning the tree of knowledge: Theory & Psychology Vol 18(6) Dec 2008, 817-828.
  • Keller, J. D., & Lehman, F. K. (1991). Complex concepts: Cognitive Science: A Multidisciplinary Journal Vol 15(2) Apr-Jun 1991, 271-291.
  • Kellogg, E. H. (1928). Review of Religion in the Making. Lowell Lectures, 1926: The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology Vol 23(3) Oct 1928, 401-406.
  • Kennedy, F. (1899). Review of The struggle for a spiritual content of life: Psychological Review Vol 6(1) Jan 1899, 92-104.
  • Keskinen, M. (2002). Hearing voices in dreams: Freud's tossing and turning with speech and writing: PsyART Vol 6 Jan-Jun 2002, No Pagination Specified.
  • Khlentzos, D. (2007). Anti-realist assumptions and challenges in philosophy of mind. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Kingsbury, F. A. (1938). Review of Naturalism in American Education: Psychological Bulletin Vol 35(7) Jul 1938, 466-467.
  • Kiverstein, J. (2005). Review of Being no-one: The self-model theory of subjectivity: Philosophical Psychology Vol 18(6) Dec 2005, 809-813.
  • Kivinen, O., & Piiroinen, T. (2004). The Relevance of Ontological Commitments in Social Sciences: Realist and Pragmatist Viewpoints: Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour Vol 34(3) Sep 2004, 231-248.
  • Knight, C., Gasevic, D., & Richards, G. (2005). Ontologies to integrate learning design and learning content: Journal of Interactive Media in Education Vol 2005(1) 2005, No Pagination Specified.
  • Kootte, A. F. (1984). A critical look at Castaneda's critics: Journal of Mind and Behavior Vol 5(1) Win 1984, 99-108.
  • Kraushaar, O. F. (1936). Lotze's influence on the psychology of William James: Psychological Review Vol 43(3) May 1936, 235-257.
  • Kuhn, R. (1994). Experience of meaning and time: Zeitschrift fur Individualpsychologie Vol 19(1) 1994, 65-73.
  • Kuras de Mauer, S., & May, N. (2001). The job of parenting: A metapsychological lecture: Psicoanalisis: Revista de la asociacion Psicoanalitica de Buenos Aires Vol 23(3) 2001, 615-624.
  • Kurtzman, H. S. (1987). Deconstructionist psychology and human liberation: A reply to Philip Wexler: New Ideas in Psychology Vol 5(1) 1987, 77-94.
  • Kusch, M. (2000). Kulpe, Oswald: Kazdin, Alan E (Ed).
  • Kvale, S. (1975). Memory and dialectics: Some reflections on Ebbinghaus and Mao Tse-tung: Human Development Vol 18(3) 1975, 205-222.
  • Lacey, N. J., & Lee, M. H. (2003). The Epistemological Foundations of Artificial Agents: Minds and Machines Vol 13(3) Aug 2003, 339-365.
  • LaChapelle, S. (2005). Attempting Science: The Creation and Early Development of the Institut Metapsychique International in Paris, 1919-1931: Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences Vol 41(1) Win 2005, 1-24.
  • Ladyman, J. (2004). Supervenience: Not local and not two-way: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 630.
  • Lane, D. A., & Maxfield, R. R. (2005). Ontological uncertainty and innovation: Journal of Evolutionary Economics Vol 15(1) Mar 2005, 3-50.
  • Laroche, J.-L. (1985). The function-presence dualism: A conversation with Henri Van Lier: Revue Quebecoise de Psychologie Vol 6(3) 1985, 22-35.
  • Laughlin, C. D. (1973). Discussion: The influence of Whitehead's organism upon Murray's personology: Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences Vol 9(3) Jul 1973, 251-257.
  • Laughlin, C. D. (1990). Womb=woman=world: Gender and transcendence in Tibetan tantric Buddhism: Journal of Prenatal & Perinatal Psychology & Health Vol 5(2) Win 1990, 147-165.
  • Leahey, T. H. (1980). The myth of operationism: Journal of Mind and Behavior Vol 1(2) Fal 1980, 127-143.
  • Leahey, T. H. (1984). Unhelpful Metaphysics: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 29 (4), Apr, 1984.
  • Leahey, T. H. (1995). Waiting for Newton: Journal of Mind and Behavior Vol 16(1) Win 1995, 9-19.
  • Leahey, T. H. (2005). What Is a Mind? II: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 50 (38), 2005.
  • Lee, J. L., & Siegel, M. D. (1996). An ontological and semantical approach to source-receiver interoperability: Decision Support Systems Vol 18(2) Oct 1996, 145-158.
  • Lesche, C. (1979). The relation between psychoanalysis and its metascience: Scandinavian Psychoanalytic Review Vol 2(1) 1979, 17-33.
  • Leuba, J. H. (1919). Religious Psychology: Psychological Bulletin Vol 16(3) Mar 1919, 63-71.
  • Levin, D. M. (1989). The listening self: Personal growth, social change and the closure of metaphysics. Florence, KY: Taylor & Frances/Routledge.
  • Levine, M. P. (2000). See no evil, hear no evil, speak no evil: Psychiatry, psychoanalysis and evil: Psychoanalytic Studies Vol 2(3) Sep 2000, 265-276.
  • Levine, N. (1976). On the metaphysics of social psychology: A critical view: Human Relations Vol 29(4) Apr 1976, 385-400.
  • Link, G. (1995). Algebraic semantics for natural language: Some philosophy, some applications: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 765-784.
  • Lloyd, A. H. (1895). Review of Introduction to the Theory of Science and Metaphysics: Psychological Review Vol 2(4) Jul 1895, 404-407.
  • Long, W. J. (2006). Quantum theory and neuroplasticity: Implications for social theory: Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology Vol 26(1-2) 2006, 78-94.
  • Lowe, E. J. (2007). Sortals and the individuation of objects: Mind & Language Vol 22(5) Nov 2007, 514-533.
  • Lowe, E. J. (2008). New directions in metaphysics and ontology: Axiomathes: An International Journal in Ontology & Cognitive Systems Vol 18(3) Sep 2008, 273-288.
  • Luquet, P. (1988). Language, thought, and psychic structure: Revue Francaise de Psychanalyse Vol 52(2) Mar-Apr 1988, 267-302.
  • Lyon, M. L. (1990). Order and healing: The concept of order and its importance in the conceptualization of healing: Medical Anthropology Vol 12(3) Aug 1990, 249-268.
  • Lyons, J. C. (2006). In Defense of Epiphenomenalism: Philosophical Psychology Vol 19(6) Dec 2006, 767-794.
  • Macdonald, G. (2004). Causation, supervenience, and special sciences: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 631.
  • MacDougall, R. (1899). Review of Psychologische Analyse der Thatsache der Selbsterziehung: Psychological Review Vol 6(5) Sep 1899, 564-566.
  • Macnamara, J. (1981). Physical objects: The relation between psychology and philosophy: Canadian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne Vol 22(3) Jul 1981, 271-281.
  • Major, R. (2000). "Desistential" psychoanalysis: Journal of European Psychoanalysis No 10-11 2000, 13-30.
  • Major, R., & Jacob, A. (2006). Cruelty, its origns, its fates: Journal of European Psychoanalysis No 23 2006, 111-125.
  • Mandler, J. M. (2008). Infant concepts revisited: Philosophical Psychology Vol 21(2) Apr 2008, 269-280.
  • Mandler, J. M. (2008). On the birth and growth of concepts: Philosophical Psychology Vol 21(2) Apr 2008, 207-230.
  • Manny, F. A. (1912). Review of Some Problems of Philosophy: A Beginning of an Introduction to Philosophy: Journal of Educational Psychology Vol 3(8) Oct 1912, 467-468.
  • Manzotti, R., & Tagliasco, V. (2004). Representation and experience: Sistemi Intelligenti Vol 16(1) Apr 2004, 63-91.
  • Marie, P. (1982). Space of expression: Notes on the acquisition of language: Neuropsychiatrie de l'Enfance et de l'Adolescence Vol 30(3) Mar 1982, 87-93.
  • Marras, A. (2004). Functionalism without multiple supervenience: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 632.
  • Martin, J. (2007). Interpreting and extending G. H. Mead's "Metaphysics" of selfhood and agency: Philosophical Psychology Vol 20(4) Aug 2007, 441-456.
  • Marvin, W. T. (1908). Review of Psychology: What is it about? and Psychology as science of self: Psychological Bulletin Vol 5(10) Oct 1908, 330-333.
  • Masuwa-Morgan, K. R., & Burrell, P. (2004). Justification of the need for an ontology for accessibility requirements (Theoretic framework): Interacting with Computers Vol 16(3) Jun 2004, 523-555.
  • McClamrock, R. (2008). The emergent, the local, and the epiphenomenal: Ecological Psychology Vol 20(3) Jul 2008, 244-251.
  • McGilvary, E. B. (1905). Review of A system of metaphysics: Psychological Bulletin Vol 2(11) Nov 1905, 373-380.
  • Menon, S. (2005). What is Indian psychology: Transcendence in and while thinking: Journal of Transpersonal Psychology Vol 37(2) 2005, 83-98.
  • Metzinger, T., & Gallese, V. (2003). The emergence of a shared action ontology: Building blocks for a theory: Consciousness and Cognition: An International Journal Vol 12(4) Dec 2003, 549-571.
  • Metzinger, T., & Gallese, V. (2003). Of course they do: Consciousness and Cognition: An International Journal Vol 12(4) Dec 2003, 574-576.
  • Meyer, A. (1907). Misconceptions at the bottom of "Hopelessness of all psychology." Psychological Bulletin Vol 4(6) Jun 1907, 170-179.
  • Mezes, S. E. (1903). Review of Die Entwicklung der Ethik. Vortrag gehalten vor der Aristotelian Society of London: Psychological Review Vol 10(1) Jan 1903, 95-96.
  • Mezes, S. E. (1906). Review of The Limits of Evolution and Other Essays Illustrating the Metaphysical Theory of Personal Idealism: Psychological Bulletin Vol 3(9) Sep 1906, 314-317.
  • Mogenson, G. (2004). Whaling with Giegerich, the Ahab of the Notion: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(1) 2004, 67-83.
  • Montague, W. P. (1903). Review of De la Realitee du Monde Sensible: Psychological Review Vol 10(4) Jul 1903, 428-432.
  • Montero, B. (2004). Really taking metaphysics seriously: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 632-633.
  • Moore, T. V. (1909). Review of Ueber die Abstraktion der Gleichheit: Psychological Bulletin Vol 6(11) Nov 1909, 385-386.
  • Morena, L. (2003). The metaphysics of material objects: Sistemi Intelligenti Vol 15(3) Dec 2003, 507-537.
  • Morrison, K. A. (1999). Proselytizing interpersonalists and imperious repairmen: Response to Schafer: Psychoanalysis & Contemporary Thought Vol 22(2) Spr 1999, 227-229.
  • Morrison, K. P. (1999). Agency, ontology, and analysis: Roy Schafer's hermeneutic conflict: Psychoanalysis & Contemporary Thought Vol 22(2) Spr 1999, 203-220.
  • Much, N. C., & Harre, R. (1994). How psychologies "secrete" moralities: New Ideas in Psychology Vol 12(3) Nov 1994, 291-321.
  • Mujica, H. (2002). About Emmanuel Levinas' Thought: Psicoanalisis: Revista de la asociacion Psicoanalitica de Buenos Aires Vol 24(3) 2002, 417-438.
  • Murdoch, J. (1842). Metaphysical philosophers. Hartford, CT: John C Wells.
  • Nash, C. B. (1963). Physical and metaphysical parapsychology: Journal of Parapsychology 27(4) 1963, 282-300.
  • Newbold, W. R. (1898). Review of Matiere et memoire: Essai sur la relation du corps a l'esprit: Psychological Review Vol 5(3) May 1898, 336-339.
  • Newell, C. (2005). Review of Human values: New essays on ethics and natural law: Nursing Ethics Vol 12(5) Sep 2005, 545-546.
  • Nicolas, S. (2002). The foundation of Fechner's psychophysics: From metaphysical presuppositions to Weber's scientific works: L'Annee Psychologique Vol 102(2) Apr-Jun 2002, 255-298.
  • Nisbett, R. E., Peng, K., Choi, I., & Norenzayan, A. (2001). Culture and systems of thought: Holistic versus analytic cognition: Psychological Review Vol 108(2) Apr 2001, 291-310.
  • No authorship, i. (1894). Review of Basal Concepts in Philosophy. An Inquiry into Being, Non-being, and Becoming: Psychological Review Vol 1(4) Jul 1894, 415-416.
  • No authorship, i. (1894). Review of Psychologie des Erkennens vom empirischen Standpunkte: Psychological Review Vol 1(3) May 1894, 301-307.
  • No authorship, i. (1895). Review of Der Begriff der Seele in der empirischen Psychologie: Psychological Review Vol 2(6) Nov 1895, 614-615.
  • No authorship, i. (1895). Review of Theorie de l'ondulation universelle; essais sur l'evolution: Psychological Review Vol 2(3) May 1895, 295.
  • No authorship, i. (1897). Review of Geschichte des Unendlichkeitsproblems im abendlandischen Denken bis Kant: Psychological Review Vol 4(5) Sep 1897, 532-535.
  • No authorship, i. (1897). Review of The Theory of Knowledge: Psychological Review Vol 4(5) Sep 1897, 529-531.
  • No authorship, i. (1905). Review of Leitfaden der Psychologie: Psychological Bulletin Vol 2(5) May 1905, 172-174.
  • No authorship, i. (1907). Review of The Dynamics of Living Matter: Psychological Bulletin Vol 4(9) Sep 1907, 291-293.
  • Noble, H. (2005). Review of A Place For Consciousness: Probing the Deep Structure of the Natural World: Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 12(4-5) Apr-May 2005, 153-156.
  • Noy, N. F., & Musen, M. A. (2003). The PROMPT suite: Interactive tools for ontology merging and mapping: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 59(6) Dec 2003, 983-1024.
  • O'Donohue, W. (1989). The (even) bolder model: The clinical psychologist as metaphysician-scientist-practitioner: American Psychologist Vol 44(12) Dec 1989, 1460-1468.
  • O'Donovan, D., & Thompson, L. G. (1965). Control, freedom, and science: Journal of Humanistic Psychology 5(1) 1965, 70-81.
  • Oku, T. (2004). A Study on Consciousness and Life Energy Based on Quantum Theory and Holographic principle: Journal of International Society of Life Information Science Vol 22(2) Sep 2004, 431-437.
  • Olson, E. T. (2007). What are we? Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Oltramari, A., Borgo, S., Catenacci, C., Ferrario, R., Gangemi, A., Guarino, N., et al. (2003). Negotiations of meaning: Sistemi Intelligenti Vol 15(3) Dec 2003, 419-428.
  • Orlov, A. B. (1988). To the problem of a dialectical paradigm in Soviet psychology: Voprosy Psychologii No 1 Jan-Feb 1988, 131-136.
  • Ormond, A. T. (1895). Review of The elements of metaphysics: Psychological Review Vol 2(2) Mar 1895, 181-184.
  • Ormond, A. T. (1903). Review of Studies in the Cartesian Philosophy: Psychological Review Vol 10(5) Sep 1903, 571-573.
  • Pateman, T. (1983). What is a language? : Language & Communication Vol 3(2) 1983, 101-127.
  • Patrick, G. T. W. (1905). Review of Elements of Metaphysics: Psychological Bulletin Vol 2(1) Jan 1905, 11-15.
  • Patrick, G. T. W. (1911). Creative Evolution: Journal of Educational Psychology Vol 2(10) Dec 1911, 582-583.
  • Paulson, D. S. (2006). Review of The perennial quest for a psychology with a soul: An inquiry into the relevance of Sri Aurobindo's metaphysical yoga psychology in the context of Ken Wilber's integral psychology: Journal of Transpersonal Psychology Vol 38(2) 2006, 251-255.
  • Peirano, M. G. (1974). Pigmy and Bantu: A study of cosmologies: Alter-Jornal de Estudos Psicodinamicos Vol 4(1-3) 1974, 60-71.
  • Penn, M. L., & Wilson, L. (2003). Mind, medicine, and metaphysics: Reflections on the reclamation of the human spirit: American Journal of Psychotherapy Vol 57(1) 2003, 18-31.
  • Pequignot, B. (1989). "The greatest strength of the present..." (Nietzsche): Psychologie Medicale Vol 21(1) Jan 1989, 106-110.
  • Perez Hernandez, C. (2002). Newton, Hume and the mechanic of the mental: Revista de Historia de la Psicologia Vol 23(3-4) 2002, 421-429.
  • Peterfreund, E. (1975). The need for a new general theoretical frame of reference for psychoanalysis: Psychoanalytic Quarterly Vol 44(4) 1975, 534-549.
  • Petitot, J. (1995). Sheaf mereology and Husserl's morphological ontology: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 741-763.
  • Pirlein, T., & Studer, R. (1995). An environment for reusing ontologies within a knowledge engineering approach: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 945-965.
  • Piscopo, C., & Birattari, M. (2008). The metaphysical character of the criticisms raised against the use of probability for dealing with uncertainty in artificial intelligence: Minds and Machines Vol 18(2) Jun 2008, 273-288.
  • Poli, R. (1995). Bimodality of formal ontology and mereology: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 687-696.
  • Poli, R. (2002). Ontological methodology: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 56(6) Jun 2002, 639-664.
  • Polkinghorne, D. E. (1994). A path of understanding for psychology: Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology Vol 14(2) Fal 1994, 128-145.
  • Postman, L. (1953). On the problem of perceptual defense: Psychological Review Vol 60(5) Sep 1953, 298-306.
  • Price, C. J., & Friston, K. J. (2005). Functional ontologies for cognition: The systematic definition of structure and function: Cognitive Neuropsychology Vol 22(3-4) May-Jun 2005, 262-275.
  • Prieto, L. (1990). A meditation on love and power: Clinica y Analisis Grupal Vol 12(1) Jan-Apr 1990, 47-52.
  • Prinz, W. (2003). Neurons don't represent: Consciousness and Cognition: An International Journal Vol 12(4) Dec 2003, 572-573.
  • Pulver, T. L. (2004). From Inflation to the Ordinary: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(1) 2004, 99-106.
  • Putnam, J. J. (1915). The necessity of metaphysics: The Journal of Abnormal Psychology Vol 10(2) Jun 1915, 88-99.
  • Pylkkanen, P. (2004). Review of Quantum Closures and Disclosures: Thinking-together Postphenomenology and Quantum Brain Dynamics: Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 11(12) Dec 2004, 89-90.
  • Pyysiainen, I. (2002). Ontology of culture and the study of human behavior: Journal of Cognition and Culture Vol 2(3) 2002, 167-182.
  • Raia, C. G. (2007). From Ether Theory to Ether Theology: Oliver Lodge and the Physics of Immortality: Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences Vol 43(1) Win 2007, 19-43.
  • Ramachandran, V. S., & Hirstein, W. (1999). Three laws of qualia: What neurology tells us about the biological functions of consciousness, qualia and the self. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Rand, B. (1923). The Early Development of Hartley's Doctrine of Association: Psychological Review Vol 30(4) Jul 1923, 306-320.
  • Raskovic, J. (1980). Ontology and psychoanalytical anthropology: Psihijatrija Danas Vol 12(4) 1980, 341-365.
  • Rendtorff, J. D. (2003). Some conceptions of evil in recent continental philosophy: Psyke & Logos Vol 24(1) 2003, 390-403.
  • Rey, G. (1985). Concepts and conceptions: A reply to Smith, Medin and Rips: Cognition Vol 19(3) Apr 1985, 297-303.
  • Ricciardi, L. M., & Umezawa, H. (2004). Brain and physics of many-body problems. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Richert, E. S. (1986). Toward the Tao of giftedness: Roeper Review Vol 8(3) Feb 1986, 197-204.
  • Riley, I. W. (1911). Historical contributions: Psychological Bulletin Vol 8(1) Jan 1911, 10-14.
  • Robinson, D. N. (1978). Lest new acquaintance be forsworn: A reply to Henle and Diamond: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 23 (10), Oct, 1978.
  • Robinson, D. N. (1989). Common sense amidst the quarks: Canadian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne Vol 30(2) Apr 1989, 185-187.
  • Rodin, A. (2004). The vessels and the glue: Space, time, and causation: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 633-634.
  • Rodrigue, E. (1985). Undine's reflections: Initial reflection: The gospel according to little John: Clinica y Analisis Grupal Vol 9(35) Feb-Mar 1985, 51-57.
  • Rosen, S. (1983). Psi-modeling and the psychophysical question: An epistemological crisis: Parapsychology Review Vol 14(1) Jan-Feb 1983, 17-24.
  • Rosengren, K. S., Johnson, C. N., & Harris, P. L. (2000). Imagining the impossible: Magical, scientific, and religious thinking in children. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Ross, D., & Spurrett, D. (2004). The cognitive and behavioral sciences: Real patterns, real unity, real causes, but no supervenience: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 637-647.
  • Ross, D., & Spurrett, D. (2004). What to say to a skeptical metaphysician: A defense manual for cognitive and behavioral scientists: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 603-627.
  • Roth, P. A. (1995). Can post-Newtonian psychologists find happiness in a pre-paradigm science? : Journal of Mind and Behavior Vol 16(1) Win 1995, 87-97.
  • Rother de Hornstein, M. C. (1987). History and project--the ego as becoming: An introduction to Piera Aulagnier's thinking: Revista de Psicoanalisis Vol 44(3) May-Jun 1987, 475-490.
  • Rottschaefer, W. A. (1999). Moral learning and moral realism: How empirical psychology illuminates issues in moral ontology: Behavior and Philosophy Vol 27(1) Spr 1999, 19-49.
  • Ryan, E. S. (2003). Chosinness and the theology of terror: Journal of Instructional Psychology Vol 30(3) Sep 2003, 237-239.
  • Rychlak, J. F. (1994). Some questions about the explanatory terminology used in any re-framing of psychology's metaphysical presuppositions: A response to Bickhard and Christopher: New Ideas in Psychology Vol 12(3) Nov 1994, 253-257.
  • Sacco, P. L. (1996). Subjective metaphysics and learning from experience: The causal psychology of rational choice: Journal of Economic Psychology Vol 17(2) Apr 1996, 221-244.
  • Sarfatti, J. (1974). Implications of meta-physics for psychoenergetic systems: Psychoenergetic Systems Vol 1(1) 1974, 3-10.
  • Scheutz, M. (2004). "Causation" is only part of the answer: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 634-635.
  • Schirmacher, W. (1984). The end of metaphysics: What does this mean? : Social Science Information/sur les sciences sociales Vol 23(3) 1984, 603-609.
  • Schmidt, W. S. (1983). Toward a cosmological foundation for pastoral care: Journal of Pastoral Care Vol 37(3) Sep 1983, 207-216.
  • Schneider, C. (1959). The Gestalt concept in ancient Greece: Zeitschrift fur Experimentelle und Angewandte Psychologie 6 1959, 335-342.
  • Schneider, K. J. (1989). Infallibility is so damn appealing: A reply to Ken Wilber: Journal of Humanistic Psychology Vol 29(4) Fal 1989, 470-481.
  • Scholl, B. J. (2007). Object persistence in philosophy and psychology: Mind & Language Vol 22(5) Nov 2007, 563-591.
  • Schouten, M. K. D. (1999). Disconnecting the concepts of consciousness: The virtues of interdisciplinarity: New Ideas in Psychology Vol 17(3) Dec 1999, 291-308.
  • Schwartz, S. P. (2006). Review of Real Natures and Familiar Objects: American Journal of Psychology Vol 119(1) Spr 2006, 139-144.
  • Schweigerdt, B. (1982). The Gnostic influence on psychology: Effects of the common heresy: Journal of Psychology & Theology Vol 10(3) Fal 1982, 221-229.
  • Scotus, D., & Wolter, A. (1962). Duns Scotus: Philosophical writings. New York, NY: Thomas Nelson and Sons.
  • Scriven, M. (1959). Physics vs paraphysics: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 4 (2), Feb, 1959.
  • Seaward, B. L. (2000). Stress and human spirituality 2000: At the cross roads of physics and metaphysics: Applied Psychophysiology and Biofeedback Vol 25(4) Dec 2000, 241-246.
  • Sellars, R. W. (1908). An important antinomy: Psychological Review Vol 15(4) Jul 1908, 237-249.
  • Sera, M. D., Gathje, J., & del Castillo Pintado, J. (1999). Language and ontological knowledge: The contrast between objects and events made by Spanish and English speakers: Journal of Memory and Language Vol 41(3) Oct 1999, 303-326.
  • Servadio, E. (1975). Mesmer's fluid: Rassegna Italiana di Ricerca Psichica Vol 1 1975-1976, 47-57.
  • Shaefer, R. (1999). Reply to Katherine Morrison: Psychoanalysis & Contemporary Thought Vol 22(2) Spr 1999, 221-226.
  • Shaffer, M. J. (2005). Review of From an Ontological Point of View: Philosophical Psychology Vol 18(2) Apr 2005, 273-277.
  • Shalizi, C. R. (2004). Functionalism, emergence, and collective coordinates: A statistical physics perspective on "What to say to a skeptical metaphysician": Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 635-636.
  • Shanahan, M. (2005). Global Access, Embodiment, and the Conscious Subject: Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 12(12) Dec 2005, 46-66.
  • Shapiro, L. A. (1997). The nature of nature: Rethinking naturalistic theories of intentionality: Philosophical Psychology Vol 10(3) Sep 1997, 309-322.
  • Shearer, E. A. (1904). Review of The Relations of Ethics to Metaphysics: Psychological Bulletin Vol 1(13) Dec 1904, 483-484.
  • Shearer, E. A. (1905). Review of La Science Positive de la Morale: Psychological Bulletin Vol 2(5) May 1905, 186-189.
  • Shedd, W. G. T. (1856). Lecture II. The nature, and definition, of secular history. Andover, MA: W F Draper.
  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1999). Phenomenology and agency: Methodological and theoretical issues in Strawson's "The Self": Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 6(4) Apr 1999, 48-69.
  • Silberstein, M. (1998). Emergence & the mind-body problem: Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 5(4) 1998, 464-482.
  • Simons, P. M., & Dell'Anna, A. (2003). Truth factors and ontological commitment: Two sides of the same semantic coin? : Sistemi Intelligenti Vol 15(3) Dec 2003, 557-569.
  • Skeen, J. W. (2002). Choice theory, virtue ethics, and the sixth need: International Journal of Reality Therapy Vol 22(1) Fal 2002, 14-19.
  • Skrupskelis, I. K. (1995). James's conception of psychology as a natural science: History of the Human Sciences Vol 8(1) Feb 1995, 73-89.
  • Slife, B. D. (1995). Introduction to "Newton's legacy for psychology." Journal of Mind and Behavior Vol 16(1) Win 1995, 1-7.
  • Slife, B. D. (2004). Taking Practice Seriously: Toward a Relational Ontology: Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology Vol 24(2) Fal 2004, 157-178.
  • Smith, B. (1995). Formal ontology, common sense and cognitive science: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 641-667.
  • Smith, B., Ceusters, W., & Morena, L. (2003). Towards industrial strength philosophy: How analytical ontology can help medical informatics: Sistemi Intelligenti Vol 15(3) Dec 2003, 407-417.
  • Smith, D. T. (1990). A (less) bolder title for the (even) bolder model: American Psychologist Vol 45(9) Sep 1990, 1084.
  • Smith, J. C., & Karmin, A. D. (2002). Idiosyncratic reality claims, relaxation dispositions, and ABC relation theory: Happiness, Literal Christianity, miraculous powers, metaphysics, and the paranormal: Perceptual and Motor Skills Vol 95(3,Pt2) Dec 2002, 1119-1128.
  • Smith, R. C. (1977). Empirical science and value assumptions: Lessons from C. G. Jung: Journal of Religion & Health Vol 16(2) Apr 1977, 102-109.
  • Solms, M. (1996). What is affect? : Psyche: Zeitschrift fur Psychoanalyse und ihre Anwendungen Vol 50(6) Jun 1996, 485-522.
  • Sorensen, A. D. (1908). Les objections au monisme: Psychological Bulletin Vol 5(7) Jul 1908, 240-241.
  • Sowa, J. F. (1995). Top level ontological categories: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 669-685.
  • Spiegelman, M. (2004). Letters to the Editor: Marvin Spiegelman, Ph.D: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(2) 2004, 62-63.
  • Stamos, D. N. (2004). Review of Discovery and decision: Exploring the metaphysics and epistemology of scientific classification: Philosophical Psychology Vol 17(1) Mar 2004, 135-139.
  • Starch, D. (1905). Deception and Reality: Psychological Bulletin Vol 2(1) Jan 1905, 15.
  • Stephenson, W. (1980). Newton's Fifth Rule and Q methodology: Application to educational psychology: American Psychologist Vol 35(10) Oct 1980, 882-889.
  • Steward, G. A., Jr., Shriver, T. E., & Chasteen, A. L. (2002). Participant narratives and collective identity in a metaphysical movement: Sociological Spectrum Vol 22(1) Jan-Mar 2002, 107-135.
  • Strawson, G. (1997). "The self." Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 4(5-6) 1997, 405-428.
  • Strawson, G. (1999). The self and the SESMET: Journal of Consciousness Studies Vol 6(4) Apr 1999, 99-135.
  • Suarez, A. (1980). Construction as ego-metaphysics: Reply to the comments of R. L. Fetz: Schweizerische Zeitschrift fur Psychologie und ihre Anwendungen/ Revue suisse de Psychologie pure et appliquee Vol 39(3) 1980, 209-220.
  • Taboada, M., Martinez, D., & Mira, J. (2005). Experiences in reusing knowledge sources using Protege and PROMPT: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 62(5) May 2005, 597-618.
  • Takala, M. (1982). The development of the concepts of man: Some starting points for the study of the history of Finnish psychology: Psykologia Vol 17(1) 1982, 30-42.
  • Tallon, A. (2007). Can Levinas's ethical metaphysics contribute to psychoanalysis? The case for and against: Psychoanalytic Review Vol 94(4) Aug 2007, 657-680.
  • Terenziani, P. (1995). Towards a causal ontology coping with the temporal constraints between causes and effects: International Journal of Human-Computer Studies Vol 43(5-6) Nov-Dec 1995, 847-863.
  • Thielst, P. (2003). Haunted by interpretations: Psyke & Logos Vol 24(1) 2003, 13-27.
  • Thornton, T. (2006). Judgement and the role of the metaphysics of values in medical ethics: Journal of Medical Ethics Vol 32(6) Jun 2006, 365-370.
  • Throne, J. M. (1973). Never Mind: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 18 (3), Mar, 1973.
  • Timpe, R. L. (1983). Epistemological and metaphysical limits to integration of psychology and theology: Journal of Psychology and Christianity Vol 2(3) Fal 1983, 21-29.
  • Tolman, C. (1981). The metaphysic of relations in Klaus Riegel's "dialectics" of human development: Human Development Vol 24(1) 1981, 33-51.
  • Tolman, C. W. (1991). Theoretical indeterminacy, pluralism and the conceptual concrete: Theory & Psychology Vol 1(2) May 1991, 147-162.
  • Tresan, D. (2007). Time is a river without banks: A response to Connolly's "Frozen time and endless analyses": The Journal of Analytical Psychology Vol 52(1) Feb 2007, 47-49.
  • Trout, J. D. (2001). Metaphysics, method, and the mouth: Philosophical lessons of speech perception: Philosophical Psychology Vol 14(3) Sep 2001, 261-291.
  • Urban, W. M. (1898). Review of Dynamic idealism; An elementary course in the metaphysic of psychology: Psychological Review Vol 5(3) May 1898, 326-328.
  • Urban, W. M. (1898). Review of Einfuhlung und association in der neueren aesthetik; Ein beitrag zur psychologischen analyse der aesthetischen anschauung: Psychological Review Vol 5(3) May 1898, 328-329.
  • Urban, W. M. (1899). L'Art et le Reel; Essai de Metaphysik fondee sur l'Esthetique: Psychological Review Vol 6(1) Jan 1899, 110-111.
  • Usatynski, T. J. (2001). Hidden assumptions of modern Western contemplative cultures: Journal of Transpersonal Psychology Vol 33(2) 2001, 131-149.
  • Valdinoci, S. (1986). Psychiatry and phenomenological psychiatry: Binswanger, a metaphysics of psychiatry: L'Evolution Psychiatrique Vol 51(4) Oct-Dec 1986, 855-870.
  • van de Vijver, G. (1997). Emergence and explanation: Intellectica No 25 1997, 7-23.
  • van de Vijver, G., Bazan, A., Rottiers, F., & Gilbert, J. (2006). Enactivism and Internalism: From Ontology to Clinics: Intellectica Vol 43(1) 2006, 93-103.
  • van Orden, G. C., Moreno, M. A., & Holden, J. G. (2003). A Proper Metaphysics for Cognitive Performance: Nonlinear Dynamics, Psychology, and Life Sciences Vol 7(1) Jan 2003, 49-60.
  • Vande Kemp, H. (1994). Psycho-spiritual dreams in the nineteenth century: II. Metaphysics and immortality: Journal of Psychology & Theology Vol 22(2) Sum 1994, 109-119.
  • Vandermeersch, P. (1992). 100 years of alienation from the foundation of things: Heymans's panpsychic hope: Psycholoog Vol 27(10) Oct 1992, 437-440.
  • Varzi, A. C. (2003). Ontology: Where it begins and where it ends: Sistemi Intelligenti Vol 15(3) Dec 2003, 493-506.
  • Vattimo, G. (2003). Masochism and Sadism: The Metaphysics of Suffering: Journal of European Psychoanalysis No 16 2003, 17-23.
  • Vattimo, G., & Lieberman, M. (2006). The Fading of Philosophy: Journal of European Psychoanalysis No 22 2006, 5-22.
  • Vercueil, L. (2002). Materialism and epilepsy: Epilepsy & Behavior Vol 3(3,Pt1) Jun 2002, 298.
  • Verene, D. P. (2002). Coincidence, historical repetition, and self-knowledge: Jung, Vico, and Joyce: The Journal of Analytical Psychology Vol 47(3) Jul 2002, 459-478.
  • Vida, J. E. (2006). On the arts: Introduction to "Presence: The touch of the puppet by Paul Zelevansky." The American Journal of Psychoanalysis Vol 66(3) Sep 2006, 261-262.
  • von Domarus, E. (1932). Die Wertheimer-Koffka-Kohlersche Gestalttheorie und das Gestaltproblem: Psychological Bulletin Vol 29(3) Mar 1932, 245-246.
  • Wakefield, J. C. (1995). When an irresistible epistemology meets an immovable ontology: Social Work Research Vol 19(1) Mar 1995, 9-17.
  • Wald, G. (1987). Consciousness and cosmology: Their interrelations. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Harwood Academic Publishers.
  • Wallace, D. (2004). Protecting cognitive science from quantum theory: Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol 27(5) Oct 2004, 636-637.
  • Walters, O. S. (1958). Metaphysics, religion, and psychotherapy: Journal of Counseling Psychology Vol 5(4) Win 1958, 243-252.
  • Warren, H. C. (1914). The mental and the physical: Psychological Review Vol 21(2) Mar 1914, 79-100.
  • Weimer, W. B. (1977). The Popper Legend, Old and New: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 22 (6), Jun, 1977.
  • Weimer, W. B. (1979). Eidlin's new logic, Heads I win, Tails you lose: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 24 (2), Feb, 1979.
  • Weimer, W. B. (1979). Two Blights don't make a right: PsycCRITIQUES Vol 24 (11), Nov, 1979.
  • Weinhold, B. K. (1979). Metaphysical approaches to helping: Elementary School Guidance & Counseling Vol 14(2) Dec 1979, 119-123.
  • Weiskopf, D. A. (2008). First thoughts: Philosophical Psychology Vol 21(2) Apr 2008, 251-268.
  • Weisskopf-Joelson, E. (1968). Was This Trip Really Necessary? : PsycCRITIQUES Vol 13 (7), Jul, 1968.
  • Wenley, R. M. (1897). Review of Outlines of Logic and Metaphysics: Psychological Review Vol 4(3) May 1897, 336-337.
  • Weslake, B. (2006). Common causes and the direction of causation: Minds and Machines Vol 16(3) Aug 2006, 239-257.
  • West, S. (1793). Introduction: West, Samuel.
  • Westcott, M. R. (1977). Free will: An exercise in metaphysical truth or psychological consequences: Canadian Psychological Review/Psychologie canadienne Vol 18(3) Jul 1977, 249-263.
  • Wettersten, J. (2007). Philosophical anthropology can help social scientists learn from empirical tests: Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour Vol 37(3) Sep 2007, 295-318.
  • Wexler, J. (2002). "Rage to order": Wallace Stevens and Hans Loewald: The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child Vol 57 2002, 458-476.
  • White, P. A. (1993). Psychological metaphysics. Florence, KY: Taylor & Frances/Routledge.
  • Wiegand, R. (2004). About progress: Zeitschrift fur Individualpsychologie Vol 29(2) 2004, 118-138.
  • Wiehl, R. (1980). Anticartesianism and the psychophysical relationship: Zeitschrift fur Klinische Psychologie und Psychotherapie Vol 28(3) 1980, 197-208.
  • Wilber, K. (1989). God is so damn boring: A response to Kirk Schneider: Journal of Humanistic Psychology Vol 29(4) Fal 1989, 457-469.
  • Wilber, K. (1989). "Infallibility is so damn appealing: A reply to Ken Wilber": Reply to Schneider: Journal of Humanistic Psychology Vol 29(4) Fal 1989, 493-500.
  • Williams, R. N. (1995). Temporality and psychological action at a distance: Journal of Mind and Behavior Vol 16(1) Win 1995, 63-75.
  • Windholz, G. (1996). Carl Ludwig Schleich, a scientist as a pseudoscientist: A psychological explanation: Imagination, Cognition and Personality Vol 16(1) 1996, 83-88.
  • Worsley, R. (2006). Emmanuel Levinas: Resource and challenge for therapy: Person-Centered and Experiential Psychotherapies Vol 5(3) Fal 2006, 208-220.
  • Wright, C. (1876). Lewes's problems of life and mind. New York, NY: Henry Holt and Co.
  • Wright, C. (1876). Limits of natural selections. New York, NY: Henry Holt and Co.
  • Wright, C. (1876). Mansel's reply to Mill. New York, NY: Henry Holt and Co.
  • Wright, C. (1876). Masson's Recent British Philosophy. New York, NY: Henry Holt and Co.
  • Wright, C. (1876). McCosh on Tyndall. New York, NY: Henry Holt and Co.
  • Wright, C. (1876). Speculative dynamics. New York, NY: Henry Holt and Co.
  • Wright, C., & Thayer, J. B. (1878). Chapter II. 1861-1865. Cambridge, MA: John Wilson & Sons.
  • Wright, C., & Thayer, J. B. (1878). Chapter III. 1865-1867. Cambridge, MA: John Wilson & Sons.
  • Wundt, W., & Judd, C. (1897). Problem of psychology. London, Great Britain; Leipzig, Germany: Williams and Norgate; Wilhelm Engelmann.
  • Xiao, X. (2004). The 1923 Scientistic Campaign and Dao-Discourse: A Cross-Cultural Study of the Rhetoric of Science: Quarterly Journal of Speech Vol 90(4) Nov 2004, 469-492.
  • Yandell, K. E. (1998). The metaphysics and morality of forgiveness. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press.
  • Zachar, P. (2003). Review of Worlds of Experience: Interweaving Philosophical and Clinical Dimensions in Psychoanalysis: Consciousness & Emotion Vol 4(2) 2003, 333-340.
  • Zahavi, D., & Parnas, J. (1999). Phenomenal consciousness and self awareness: A phenomenological critique of representational theory. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Zaman, L. F., III. (2002). Nature's psychogenic forces: Localized quantum consciousness: Journal of Mind and Behavior Vol 23(4) Fal 2002, 351-374.
  • Zelevansky, P. (2006). Presence: The touch of the puppet: The American Journal of Psychoanalysis Vol 66(3) Sep 2006, 263-288.
  • Zuriff, G. (1998). Against metaphysical social constructionism in psychology: Behavior and Philosophy Vol 26(1-2) Spr-Fal 1998, 5-28.
  • Zusne, L. (1965). Metaphysical parallels of the study of values: Psychological Record 15(4) 1965, 537-543.


Additional material[]

Books[]

  • Abbot, F. E. (1885). The principles of Scientific Theism. New York, NY: Little, Brown and Co.
  • Abbot, F. E. (1885). The universe: Machine or organism? New York, NY: Little, Brown and Co.
  • Abercrombie, J. (1841). Abstraction. London, England: John Murray.
  • Adler, H. E. (1993). William James and Gustav Fechner: From rejection to elective affinity. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
  • Albanese, C. L. (2007). A republic of mind and spirit: A cultural history of American metaphysical religion. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
  • Bascom, J. (1871). Lecture II. Primitive ideas; their relation to knowledge. New York, NY: G P Putnam & Sons, Publishers.
  • Bascom, J. (1871). Lecture IV. Resemblance not the sole law of thought. New York, NY: G P Putnam & Sons, Publishers.
  • Bascom, J. (1871). Lecture IX. Life; its nature and origin. -- The mind. New York, NY: G P Putnam & Sons, Publishers.
  • Bascom, J. (1871). Lecture V. Matter; its existence and nature. New York, NY: G P Putnam & Sons, Publishers.
  • Bascom, J. (1871). Lecture VI. Consciousness, the field of mental facts. New York, NY: G P Putnam & Sons, Publishers.
  • Bascom, J. (1871). Lecture VII. Right, the law of intellectual life. New York, NY: G P Putnam & Sons, Publishers.
  • Bascom, J. (1871). Lecture VIII. Liberty. New York, NY: G P Putnam & Sons, Publishers.
  • Bascom, J. (1871). Lecture X. Interaction of physical forces and spiritual powers. New York, NY: G P Putnam & Sons, Publishers.
  • Bascom, J. (1871). Lecture XI. Primitive religious conceptions. New York, NY: G P Putnam & Sons, Publishers.
  • Bascom, J. (1871). Lecture XII. Classification of knowledge: Form of development. New York, NY: G P Putnam & Sons, Publishers.
  • Bloom, P. (2007). Water as an artifact kind. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Browning, D. S. (2002). Science and religion on the nature of love. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Capen, N. (1881). Metaphysics before the time of Gall--physiognomy nothing without phrenology. New York, NY: Fowler and Wells.
  • Chalmers, T. (1833). On the general adaptation of external nature to the moral constitution of man. London, Great Britain: William Pickering.
  • Chalmers, T. (1833). On the power wisdom and goodness of God as manifested in the adaptation of external nature to the moral and intellectual constitution of man, Vol 1. London, Great Britain: William Pickering.
  • Chalmers, T. (1833). On the special and subordinate adaptations of external nature to the moral constitution of man. London, Great Britain: William Pickering.
  • Davis, H. T. (1953). Is there an ether? Bloomington, IN: Principia Press.
  • Davis, H. T. (1953). The quantum theory and wave mechanics. Bloomington, IN: Principia Press.
  • Davis, H. T. (1953). Time, space, and the fourth dimension. Bloomington, IN: Principia Press.
  • Day, H. N. (1877). Elements of psychology. New York, NY: G P Putnam's Sons.
  • Day, H. N. (1877). Existence. New York, NY: G P Putnam's Sons.
  • Globus, G. (2004). Dual mode ontology and its application to the Riemann Hypothesis. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Globus, G. G. (2003). Quantum closures and disclosures: Thinking-together postphenomenology and quantum brain dynamics. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Globus, G. G., Pribram, K. H., & Vitiello, G. (2004). Brain and being: At the boundary between science, philosophy, language and arts. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Hayward, J. (1999). A rDzogs-chen Buddhist interpretation of the sense of self. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Cause and effect. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Conclusion. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Contingence. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Edward's definition of will. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Freedom of mind in willing; or, Every being that wills a creative first cause. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). God's foreknowledge. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Illustration from chess. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Liberty as defined by Edwards. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Liberty, or freedom. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Of cause. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Of effort for internal change. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Of matter as cause. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Of mind. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Of spirit as cause. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Of the existence of matter. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Of the existence of spirit. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Of the will. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Of want. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Of want and effort in various orders of intelligence. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1866). Relation of indifference to freedom in willing. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1883). First discourse: Man as a creative first cause. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1883). Man: A creative first cause, two discourses. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1884). Man a creative first cause, two discourses delivered at Concord, Mass, July 1882 (2nd ed.). Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Hazard, R. G. (1884). Second discourse: Man, in the sphere of his own moral nature, a supreme creative first cause. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Hazard, R. G., & Hazard, C. (1889). Discourse I. Man a creative first cause. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Hedge, L. (1824). General description of demonstrative reasoning. Boston, MA: Cummings, Hilliard & Co.
  • Hegel, G. W. F., & Wallace, W. (1892). First attitude of thought to objectivity. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Hegel, G. W. F., & Wallace, W. (1892). Second attitude of thought to objectivity. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Hegel, G. W. F., & Wallace, W. (1892). Second subdivision of logic. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Heidelberger, M. (2007). Freedom and science! The presumptuous metaphysics of free-will disdainers. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers.
  • Heil, J. (2003). Multiply realized properties. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Hickok, L. P. (1872). Antagonist force. Boston, MA: Lee and Shepard.
  • Hickok, L. P. (1872). Diremptive force. Boston, MA: Lee and Shepard.
  • Hickok, L. P. (1872). Force. Boston, MA: Lee and Shepard.
  • Hickok, L. P. (1872). Life. Boston, MA: Lee and Shepard.
  • Hickok, L. P. (1872). The reign of life in the vegetable kingdom. Boston, MA: Lee and Shepard.
  • Hickok, L. P. (1872). Revolving force. Boston, MA: Lee and Shepard.
  • Hiley, B. J. (2004). Information, quantum theory and the brain. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Hill, O. A. (1921). Thesis I. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hill, O. A. (1921). Thesis II. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hill, O. A. (1921). Thesis III. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hill, O. A. (1921). Thesis IV. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hill, O. A. (1921). Thesis VI. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hill, O. A. (1921). Thesis VIII. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hill, O. A. (1921). Thesis XII. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Hill, O. A. (1921). Thesis XIII. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Johnson, A. B. (1836). Lecture I.--Introductory. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Johnson, A. B. (1836). Lecture II.--External sensible existences are susceptible of a classification which shall refer each existence to the sense through whose agency we acquire our knowledge of the existence. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Johnson, A. B. (1836). Lecture III.--Language implies a oneness to which nature conforms not in all cases. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Johnson, A. B. (1836). Lecture V.--Language implies identities to which nature conforms not. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Johnson, A. B. (1836). Lecture XIX.--Every question which relates to the external universe is insignificant, if it cannot be answered by our senses. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Johnson, A. B. (1836). Lecture XX.--Every question which relates to what is internal of man, is insignificant if it cannot be answered by our consciousness. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Johnson, A. B. (1836). Lecture XXI.--Inquiries after a theory we mistake for an investigation of nature. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Johnson, A. B. (1836). Lecture XXIX.--We mistake words for the ultimate objects of knowledge, while the revelations of nature are properly the ultimate objects. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Johnson, A. B. (1836). Lecture XXVI.--We mistake the unintelligibility of a word or proposition for a mystery of nature. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Johnson, A. B. (1836). Lecture XXVIII.--We mistake the inapplicability of a process of language for a defect or mystery of nature. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Johnson, A. B. (1836). Treatise on language: or, The relation which words bear to things, in four parts. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Johnson, C. N. (2000). Putting different things together: The development of metaphysical thinking. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Johnson, S. (1754). The author's preface to the Philadelphia edition, 1752. London, Great Britain: A Millar.
  • Johnson, S. (1754). The elements of philosophy: containing, I. The most useful parts of logic, including both metaphysics and dialectic, or the art of reasoning: with a brief account of the progress of the mind towards its highest perfection, to which is prefixed a short introduction to the study of the sciences; II. A brief view both of the speculative and practical part of moral philosophy, as improved by Christianity, to which is added an original letter concerning the settlement of bishops in America (3rd ed.). London, Great Britain: A Millar.
  • Johnson, S. (1754). An introduction to the study of philosophy. Exhibiting a general view of all the parts of learning. London, Great Britain: A Millar.
  • Johnson, S. (1754). Of the author of our nature, his perfections and operations. London, Great Britain: A Millar.
  • Johnson, S. (1754). Of the duties in general, resulting from the foregoing truths. London, Great Britain: A Millar.
  • Johnson, S. (1754). Of the duties which we owe to ourselves. London, Great Britain: A Millar.
  • Johnson, S. (1754). Of the end of our being, and of our future state. London, Great Britain: A Millar.
  • Johnson, S. (1754). Of the mind simply apprehending, and of its objects more particularly. London, Great Britain: A Millar.
  • Johnson, S. (1754). Of the nature of man, his excellencies and imperfections. London, Great Britain: A Millar.
  • Keil, F. C., Greif, M. L., & Kerner, R. S. (2007). A world apart: How concepts of the constructed world are different in representation and in development. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Kelemen, D., & Carey, S. (2007). The essence of artifacts: Developing the design stance. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Kornblith, H. (2007). How to refer to artifacts. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1887). The mind as real being. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1890). Metaphysics. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1894). Consciousness and self-consciousness. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1895). The concept of mind. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1895). Mind and body. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1895). Monism and dualism. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1895). Origin and permanence of mind. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1895). Philosophy of mind: An essay in the metaphysics of psychology. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1895). Place of man's mind in nature. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1895). Psychology and the philosophy of mind. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1895). Psychology and the philosophy of mind (continued). New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Ladd, G. T. (1895). The unity of mind. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Laycock, S. W. (1999). Consciousness it/self. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Laycock, T. (1860). Matter and mind. Edinburgh, Scotland: Sutherland and Knox.
  • Laycock, T. (1860). On fundamental intuitions as scientific ideas, or causal ideas of the sciences. Edinburgh, Scotland: Sutherland and Knox.
  • Laycock, T. (1860). The subject continued. Restrictions on the progress of mental science from the prejudices of mankind and the dogmas of speculative metaphysics and theology. Edinburgh, Scotland: Sutherland and Knox.
  • Levinson, J. (2007). Artworks as artifacts. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Levy-Valensi, E. A. (1996). The emergence of sense. Jerusalem, Israel: Magnes Press.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1871). First epoch. Speculations on the nature of the universe. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1871). Second epoch. Foundation of the deductive method. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1871). Second epoch. Speculations on the creation of the universe, and on the origin of knowledge. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1871). Seventh epoch. Philosophy again, reduced to a system: Close of the Socratic movement.--Aristotle. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1873). The conflict of opinion and the issue. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1873). Ideal constructions in metaphysics. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1873). Intuition and demonstration. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1873). The method. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1873). Objections to metaphysics. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1873). The place of metaphysics among the sciences. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1873). Problems of life and mind. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1873). The search after causes. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1873). Some observations on Kant. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin and Company.
  • Lewes, G. H. (1877). The physical basis of mind. Boston, MA: James R Osgood and Company.
  • Lupton, D. (1999). Risk and the ontology of pregnant embodiment. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Malt, B. C., & Sloman, S. A. (2007). Artifact categorization: The good, the bad, and the ugly. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Mandler, J. M. (2007). The conceptual foundations of animals and artifacts. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Mansel, H. L. (1866). I. Psychology, or the philosophy of the phenomena of consciousness. London, Great Britain: Adam and Charles Black.
  • Mansel, H. L. (1866). II. Ontology; or the philosophy of the realities of consciousness. London, Great Britain: Adam and Charles Black.
  • Mansel, H. L. (1866). Metaphysics, or the philosophy of consciousness, phenomenal and real (2nd ed.). London, Great Britain: Adam and Charles Black.
  • Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (2007). Creations of the mind: Theories of artifacts and their representation. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Maudsley, H. (1867). On the method of the study of mind. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Maudsley, H. (1884). Body and will, being an essay concerning will in its metaphysical, physiological, and pathological aspects. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Maudsley, H. (1884). Concerning the authority of consciousness. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • McCosh, J. (1872). The mental sciences. New York, NY: Hurst & Company Publishers.
  • McCosh, J. (1872). Metaphysics, gnosiology, and ontology. New York, NY: Hurst & Company Publishers.
  • McDougall, W. (1915). The unity of consciousness. London, Great Britain: Methuen & Co.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1860). Book I. Metaphysics. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1860). Book II. Metaphysical principles involved in the sciences. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1866). Causation. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1866). An examination of Mr. J. S. Mill's philosophy; being a defence of fundamental truth. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1866). Introduction--Sir William Hamilton and Mr. Mill. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1866). Man's power of conception as a test. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1866). Mr. Mill's admissions. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1866). What is truth? Criteria of truth. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1875). Causation. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1875). The method of investigation. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1875). Mr. Mill's admissions. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1875). Relativity of knowledge. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • M'Cosh, J. (1875). What is truth? Criteria of truth. New York, NY: Robert Carter & Brothers.
  • Mill, J. S. (1867). An examination of Sir William Hamilton's philosophy and of the principal philosophical questions discussed in his writings (3rd ed.). London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1867). How Sir William Hamilton and Mr. Mansel dispose of the law of inseparable association. London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1867). Of consciousness, as understood by Sir William Hamilton. London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1867). On the freedom of the will. London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1867). The philosophy of the conditioned, as applied by Mr. Mansel to the limits of religious thought. London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1867). The relativity of human knowledge. London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1867). Sir William Hamilton's view of the different theories respecting the belief in an external world. London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1875). Of progressive effects; and of the continued action of causes. London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1875). Of the evidence of the law of universal causation. London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1875). Of the extension of derivative laws to adjacent cases. London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1875). Of the logic of practice, or art; including morality and policy. London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1875). Of the remaining laws of nature. London, Great Britain: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, J. S. (1884). Concluding remarks. Ny: Henry Holt and Company.
  • Mill, J. S. (1884). How Sir W. Hamilton and Mr. Mansel dispose of the law of inseparable association. Ny: Henry Holt and Company.
  • Mill, J. S. (1884). In what respect Sir W. Hamilton really differs from the philosophers of the absolute. Ny: Henry Holt and Company.
  • Mill, J. S. (1884). The relativity of human knowledge. Ny: Henry Holt and Company.
  • Mill, J. S. (1884). Sir W. Hamilton's opinions on the study of mathematics. Ny: Henry Holt and Company.
  • Mill, J. S. (1884). Sir W. Hamilton's view of the different theories respecting the belief in an external world. Ny: Henry Holt and Company.
  • Miller, A. (2006). Realism and antirealism. New York, NY: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.
  • Miller, D. L. (2004). The End of Ending: A Response to Wolfgang Giegerich: Journal of Jungian Theory and Practice Vol 6(1) 2004, 85-93.
  • Mills, F. B. (2001). A Spinozist approach to the conceptual gap in consciousness studies: Journal of Mind and Behavior Vol 22(1) Win 2001, 91-102.
  • Mills, J. (2003). Whitehead's unconscious ontology: Theory & Psychology Vol 13(2) Apr 2003, 209-238.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). Containing a general view of the mental system. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). Containing a general view of the various kinds of true perception. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). Containing practical remarks on that divine operation, which extends to every part of the material universe. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). Containing recapitulatory remarks on perception. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On abstract or general ideas. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On divine agency. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On infinite perfection. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On propositions, possibility, necessity, contingence, and truth, actual and conditional. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On sensation. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the death of the body, and the final transition of the soul from time to eternity. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the divine decrees. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the divine economy of redemption. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the divine happiness. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the divine knowledge. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the divine mind. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the divine perception. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the divine power. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the extent of the universe. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the general properties of matter. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the nature and essence of the finite mind. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the nature of belief, and its various objects. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the nature of causes and effects. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the nature of common and special volition. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the nature of life and death, in relation to the finite mind. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the origin and the nature of number and place. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the particular cause of perception. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the perception of falsehood, and false perception. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the primitive cause of circular motion. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the sacred scriptures. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the universal laws of circular motion. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On the will; together with the nature and use of motives. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). On time and eternity. Osborn, Benjamin. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Osborn, B. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts. (1816). Truth displayed: In a series of elementary principles, illustrated and enforced by practical observations, in three parts.
  • Palmer, E. (1824). Nature of existence, predicament of man in the universe, ancient and modern opinions upon the subject. London, England: R Carlile.
  • Pearson, K. (1892). The laws of motion. London, England; New York, NY: Walter Scott Publishing Co; Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Pearson, K. (1892). Life. London, England; New York, NY: Walter Scott Publishing Co; Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Porter, N. (1882). Autobiography of John Stuart Mill. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Porter, N. (1882). Physiological metaphysics; or, the apotheosis of science by suicide. A philosophical meditation. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Porter, N. (1886). Brief notices from a few of Kant's German critics. Chicago, IL: S C Griggs and Company.
  • Porter, N. (1886). The Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals. Chicago, IL: S C Griggs and Company.
  • Romanes, G. J. (1895). Materialism. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • Romanes, G. J. (1895). Mind and motion and monism. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • Romanes, G. J. (1895). Monism. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • Romanes, G. J. (1895). Spiritualism. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • Romanes, G. J. (1895). The will in relation to materialism and spiritualism. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • Romanes, G. J. (1895). The will in relation to monism. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • Romanes, G. J. (1895). The world as an eject. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
  • Romanes, G. J., & Gore, C. (1902). The influence of science upon religion. Chicago, IL: Open Court Publishing Co.
  • Romanes, G. J., & Gore, C. (1902). Thoughts on religion (5th ed.). Chicago, IL: Open Court Publishing Co.
  • Rush, J. (1865). Brief outline of an analysis of the human intellect; intended to rectify the scholastic and vulgar perversions of the natural purpose, and method of thinking; by rejecting altogether the theoretic confusion, the unmeaning arrangement, and indefinite nomenclature of the metaphysician (Vol 1). Philadelphia, PA: J B Lippincott Company.
  • Rush, J. (1865). Containing terms, divisions, and explanations; with a view of the subjects of materialism, spirituality, and of instinct. Philadelphia, PA: J B Lippincott Company.
  • Rush, J. (1865). Of the division of language into the parts of speech. Philadelphia, PA: J B Lippincott Company.
  • Saltus, E. (1889). The dissent of the seers. Chicago, IL: Belford, Clarke & Company.
  • Saltus, E. (1889). The protests of yesterday. Chicago, IL: Belford, Clarke & Company.
  • Saltus, E. (1889). The revolt of the orient. Chicago, IL: Belford, Clarke & Company.
  • Saltus, E. (1889). Then anatomy of negation (rev. ed.). Chicago, IL: Belford, Clarke & Company.
  • Schmucker, S. S. (1842). Of objective entities as subjects of our knowledge. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Schwegler, A., & Seelye, J. H. (1856). The Eleatics. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Schwegler, A., & Seelye, J. H. (1856). The Ionic philosophers. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Schwegler, A., & Seelye, J. H. (1856). New Platonism. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Schwegler, A., & Seelye, J. H. (1856). Pythagoreanism. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Shuger, D. K. (2004). The Philosophical Foundations of Sacred Rhetoric. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Silva, T. (2005). On the Philosophical Bases of Inquiry in Second Language Writing: Metaphysics, Inquiry Paradigms, and the Intellectual Zeitgeist. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers.
  • Spencer, H. (1872). The assumption of metaphysicians. London, Great Britain: Williams and Norgate.
  • Spencer, H. (1872). A criterion wanted. London, Great Britain: Williams and Norgate.
  • Spencer, H. (1872). The final question. London, Great Britain: Williams and Norgate.
  • Spencer, H. (1872). Imperfect qualitative reasoning. London, Great Britain: Williams and Norgate.
  • Spencer, H. (1872). Its corollaries. London, Great Britain: Williams and Norgate.
  • Spencer, H. (1872). Perfect qualitative reasoning. London, Great Britain: Williams and Norgate.
  • Spencer, H. (1872). The reasonings of metaphysicians. London, Great Britain: Williams and Norgate.
  • Spencer, H. (1872). The words of metaphysicians. London, Great Britain: Williams and Norgate.
  • Spencer, H. (1910). The composition of mind. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Spencer, H. (1910). Part VII. General analysis. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Spencer, H. (1910). The substance of mind. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Sperber, D. (2007). Seedless grapes: Nature and culture. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Sponheim, P. R. (2001). Meaning and the tenses of time: A Whiteheadian perspective. New York, NY: Springer Publishing Co.
  • Spurzheim, J. G. (1855). Phrenology, or the Doctrine of the mental phenomena, Vol 2: Philosophical part. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Stamenov, M. I. (2004). The rheomode of language of David Bohm as a way to re-construct the access to physical reality. Amsterdam, Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Stenger, V. J. (2007). God: The failed hypothesis. How science shows that God does not exist. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.
  • Sterrett, J. M. (1890). The absolute religion. New York, NY: D Appleton & Company.
  • Strawson, G. (1999). "The self". Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Strong, C. A. (1903). Automatist theories. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Strong, C. A. (1903). Consciousness. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Strong, C. A. (1903). Interactionist theories. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Strong, C. A. (1903). Parallelist theories. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Strong, C. A. (1903). The physical world. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Stuart, S. A. J. (2007). Unifying experience: Imagination & self-consciousness. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
  • Swedenborg, E., & Acton, A. (1923). The existence of the human soul. Wolff's rules. Philadelphia, PA: Swedenborg Scientific Association.
  • Swedenborg, E., & Acton, A. (1923). How to acquire a knowledge of the soul. Philadelphia, PA: Swedenborg Scientific Association.
  • Taylor, I. (1858). Distribution of the subject. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Taylor, I. (1858). Metaphysics: Concretive abstractions. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Taylor, I. (1858). Metaphysics: Grounds of certainty in relation to metaphysical speculation. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Taylor, I. (1858). Metaphysics: Mixed abstractions. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Taylor, I. (1858). Metaphysics: The sense of fitness and order. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Taylor, I. (1858). Metaphysics: Ultimate abstractions. New York, NY: Harper & Brothers.
  • Thomasson, A. L. (2007). Artifacts and human concepts. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Troward, T. (1909). The body. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). Causes and conditions. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). The Edinburgh lectures on mental science. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). Further considerations regarding subjective and objective mind. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). The higher mode of intelligence controls the lower. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). In touch with sub-conscious mind. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). Intuition. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). The law of growth. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). Receptivity. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). Reciprocal action of the universal and individual minds. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). The soul. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). The spirit. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). Spirit and matter. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). Subjective and objective mind. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). The unity of the spirit. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Troward, T. (1909). The will. New York, NY: Robert M McBride & Co.
  • Tucker, A. (1805). The light of nature pursued, (2nd ed. rev. and corrected), together with some account of the life of the author (Vol 3). London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Chance, necessity, and design. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Compound substances. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Divisibility of matter. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Duration of mind. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Effects and causes. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Equity. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Eternity. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Existence of mind. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). External nature. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). The first cause. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Goodness. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Incomprehensibility. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Mundane soul. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Omnipotence. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Omnipresence. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Omniscience. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Spirit. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Substance. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Two characters in God. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Unity. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tucker, A., & Mildmay, H. P. S. J. (1805). Vehicular state. London, England; London, England: R Faulder; T Payne.
  • Tunner, W. (1994). Schopenhauer's ethics and the concept of behavioral self-regulation. New York, NY: Plenum Press.
  • Unzer, J. A., & Laycock, T. (1851). The reciprocal connection of the body with the soul. London, Great Britain: Sydenham Society.
  • von Hartmann, E., & Coupland, W. C. (1893). Philosophy of the unconscious: Speculative results according to the inductive method of physical science, Vol. 3 (2nd ed.). London, England: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Company.
  • Waite, C. B. (1900). Doctrine of the unknowable--antithesis of thought. Chicago, IL: C V Waite & Co.
  • Waite, C. B. (1900). Doctrine of the unknowable--idealism. Chicago, IL: C V Waite & Co.
  • Waite, C. B. (1900). The new philosophy--Doctrine of the unknowable. Chicago, IL: C V Waite & Co.
  • Waite, C. B. (1900). Reconciliation between science and religion. Chicago, IL: C V Waite & Co.
  • Waite, C. B. (1900). Space and time--consciousness. Chicago, IL: C V Waite & Co.
  • Waite, C. B. (1900). Spencer and John Stuart Mill. Chicago, IL: C V Waite & Co.
  • Ward, J. (1899). Lecture XIV. General conception of experience. London, Great Britain: Adam and Charles Black.
  • Ward, J. (1899). Lecture XV. Experience as life. London, Great Britain: Adam and Charles Black.
  • Ward, J. (1899). Lecture XX. Spiritualistic monism. London, Great Britain: Adam and Charles Black.
  • Ward, L. F. (1892). The economy of nature and the economy of mind. Boston, MA: Ginn & Company.
  • Washington, W. M. (1898). The fundamental principles of the metaphysic of morals. New York, NY: MacMillan Co.
  • Watts, I. (1742). On some metaphysical subjects. London, Great Britain: James Brackstone.
  • Wax, S. (2007). Placing god before me: Spirituality and responsibility at work. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
  • Wentworth, J. B. (1886). Induction the accredited method. New York, NY: Phillips & Hunt.
  • Wesson, R. (1989). Cosmos and metacosmos. Chicago, IL: Open Court Publishing Co.
  • West, S. (1793). Essay I. Concerning the nature of that liberty or freedom, which is maintained in these essays: West, Samuel.
  • West, S. (1793). Essay II. That volition is not properly an effect, which has a cause: West, Samuel.
  • West, S. (1793). Essay III. The divine prescience does not imply the necessity of future events: West, Samuel.
  • West, S. (1793). Essays on liberty and necessity; in which the true nature of liberty is stated and defended; and the principal arguments used by Mr. Edwards, and others, for necessity, are considered: (1793) Essays on liberty and necessity; in which the true nature of liberty is stated and defended; and the principal arguments used by Mr.

Papers[]

Dissertations[]

  • Albert, D. B. (1994). Event horizons of the psyche: Synchronicity, psychedelics, and the metaphysics of consciousness. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Allen, K. (1984). Personal identity: An epistemological assessment and a metaphysical theory: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Anderson, R. L. (2007). Functional ontology construction: A pragmatic approach to addressing problems concerning the individual and the informing environment. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Baillie, H. W. (1978). The psychological foundation of Aristotelian wisdom: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Barasinski, J. B. (1993). A metaphysical experience of the Absolute: A study of a theistic experience in the light of Edmund Husserl's phenomenological method: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Beckman, K. R. (1999). Vanishing women. (stage magic, psychoanalysis, Sir Alfred Hitchcock, England, Veit Harlan, Germany, Bette Davis, women). Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Blom, J. J. (1975). A systematic study of the mind-body relation according to Descartes: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Brown, B. T. (1995). Metaphysics and schizophrenics: A comprehensive analysis of the thought of R. D. laing and its implications for sociological theory. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Cavers-Huff, D. Y. (1997). Cognitive science and metaphysics revisited: Toward a theory of properties. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Chalmers, D. J. (1994). Toward a theory of consciousness. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Coelho, A. J. (1994). Mandalas within-beyond life: A phenomenological investigation into life and revelation as gifts unfolding-enfolding. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • David, G. L. (1975). Logical positivism, the mind-body problem and immortality: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Field, R. A. (1982). The return of the goddess: The feminine principle in the theosophic thought and transpersonal psychology: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Finn, G. (2000). The concept of the order of nature in the philosophy of Spinoza: An analysis from the perspective of Justus Buchler's ordinal metaphysics. (Baruch Spinoza). Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Gillespie, D. (1982). An interpretation of some metatheoretical assumptions in cognitive psychology: Mechanism and contextualism: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Haney, S. R. (1993). Time and knowledge in William Faulkner's "Absalom, Absalomp": Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Heil, J. F., Jr. (1996). Minds, bodies and affections: Plato and Aristotle on the metaphysics of the mental. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Hickey, L. P. (1999). An interpretation and defense of social externalism. (Hilary Putnam, externalism, normativity, metaphysical realism). Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Isley, C. T. (1997). Intentionality, experience, and the lifeworld: Phenomenological presupposition and the challenge of contemporary scientism. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Jalava, J. V. (2008). Science of conscience: Metaphysics, morality, and rhetoric in psychopathy research. Dissertation Abstracts International: Section B: The Sciences and Engineering.
  • Jecmen, D. J. (1994). Toward an integration of spirituality and psychology: A contribution from metaphysical tradition. Dissertation Abstracts International: Section B: The Sciences and Engineering.
  • Kaczynski, R. P. (1994). The structure and correlates of metaphysical beliefs among a sample of behaviorally committed participants. Dissertation Abstracts International: Section B: The Sciences and Engineering.
  • Kelly, D. R. (2008). Projectivism psychologized: The philosophy and psychology of disgust. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Kuhar, R. M. (2006). An exploration of the impact of education and engagement in science on scientists' metaphysical beliefs and spirituality. Dissertation Abstracts International: Section B: The Sciences and Engineering.
  • Lizza, J. P. (1992). Metaphysical and cultural aspects of persons: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Lyon, K. (1992). Context effects and the structure of concepts: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • McGarry, K., Garfield, S., & Morris, N. (2006). Recent trends in knowledge and data integration for the life sciences: Expert Systems: International Journal of Knowledge Engineering and Neural Networks Vol 23(5) Nov 2006, 330-341.
  • McGrattan, C. (2006). The psychology of "A Course in Miracles" in secular and metaphysical contexts. Dissertation Abstracts International: Section B: The Sciences and Engineering.
  • Mellick, D. C. (1974). The metaphysics of behavior: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Milne, A. (1997). The alienation of content: Truth, rationality and mind. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences
  • Pascoe, J. P. (1979). A metatheoretical analysis of psychological and Christian thought for the purpose of formulating an integrative psychology: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Prane, J. Z. (2000). Multiple Personality Disorder/Dissociated Identity Disorder: The client as actor model. Dissertation Abstracts International: Section B: The Sciences and Engineering.
  • Ray, C. (1999). Identity and universals: A conceptualist approach to logical, metaphysical, and epistemological problems of contemporary identity theory. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Reginster, B. M. (1992). Nietzsche on the nature and necessity of a psychological critique of metaphysics: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Ross, P. W. (1998). Being red and seeing red: Sensory and perceptible qualities. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Schroll, M. A. (1998). The philosophical legacy of David Bohm, its relationship to transpersonal psychology and the emergence of ecopsychology: Searching for a coherent, co-evolutionary, sustainable culture. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Simmons, A. J. (1995). Making sense: The problem of phenomenal qualities in late scholastic Aristotelianism and Descartes. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Szendre, E. N. (1996). Children's assignment of intentionality to people, animals, plants, and objects: Challenges to theory of mind and animism. Dissertation Abstracts International: Section B: The Sciences and Engineering.
  • Thompson, D. F. (1982). Ethics of metaphysics and ethics of value: A study in the thought of Bernard Lonergan: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Vernon, R. F. (2003). The therapy relationship: Developing a sound metaphysical description of personal relations. Dissertation Abstracts International: Section B: The Sciences and Engineering.
  • Wachsberg, M. M. (1983). Personal identity, the nature of persons, and ethical theory: Dissertation Abstracts International.
  • Wang, W.-F. (1997). Non-actualism. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Yun, D. Y. (1998). Quine's criterion of ontological reduction. Dissertation Abstracts International Section A: Humanities and Social Sciences.
  • Zelman, R. P. (2003). Experiential philosophy: Metaphysics and altered states of consciousness. Dissertation Abstracts International: Section B: The Sciences and Engineering.

External links[]


  1. redirectTemplate:Philosophy
This page uses Creative Commons Licensed content from Wikipedia (view authors).
Advertisement